Abstract
Before there was a culture war in the United States over same-sex marriage, there was a battle between opponents and proponents of same-sex marriage within the LGBTQ+ community. Some opposed same-sex marriage because of the long patriarchal history of marriage and the more consequential need to bridge the economic and privilege gap between the married and the unmarried. Others, in contrast, saw marriage as a civil rights issue and lauded the transformative potential of same-sex marriage, contending that it could upset the patriarchal nature of marriage and help to refashion marriage into something new and better.
This Article looks back at that debate—and explores the complex relationship between legal and social change—through the prism of the federal tax definition of marriage before and after the landmark decisions in United States v. Windsor and Obergefell v. Hodges. Through an examination of the Internal Revenue Service’s shifting positions regarding the recognition of civil unions and domestic partnerships, this Article explores how and why the promised transformative potential of same-sex marriage has failed to be realized in this influential area of law.
I. Introduction
Before there was a culture war in the United States over same-sex marriage, there was a debate between opponents and proponents of same-sex marriage within the LGBTQ+ community. Some within the community opposed pursuing the right to marry because of the long patriarchal history of marriage and the more consequential need to bridge the economic and privilege gap between the married and the unmarried. Others, however, saw marriage as a civil rights issue because of the central importance of marriage in American society. They sensed a profound wrong in denying marriage to same-sex couples who carried on lives no different from their heterosexual counterparts. Marriage proponents also lauded same-sex marriage’s transformative potential, contending that it would contribute to refashioning marriage into something new, better, and less patriarchal. Opponents, of course, feared the hegemony of heterosexual marriage and argued that same-sex marriage could not and would not transform American society.
This Article looks back at this debate through the lens of the federal tax definition of marriage before and after the U.S. Supreme Court’s decisions in United States v. Windsor and Obergefell v. Hodges, which legalized same-sex marriage in the federal and state realms, respectively. Following the advent of marriage equality, the question is whether the promised transformative potential of same-sex marriage is being realized. In the realm of federal tax law—the situs of perhaps the most intimate and sustained connection that citizens have with government—the answer thus far is a resounding no.
After earlier opening the door to legally recognizing a broader array of relationships, the Internal Revenue Service (Service) reversed course in the wake of Windsor and refused recognition to any relationship not denominated marriage. At first, it seemed that the Service was prodding states that had adopted civil union or domestic partnership regimes to recognize same-sex marriage—and this did happen in the two years that separated the Windsor and Obergefell decisions. But after Obergefell, when every state was required to permit same-sex couples to marry, the Service even more firmly closed the door to recognizing alternative relationship statuses, revealing its original move as reactionary and aimed at stymieing the transformative potential of same-sex marriage in this influential area of the law. This Article approaches the collision between faith in the ability to disrupt and overturn hierarchies and the reality of powerful and entrenched societal institutions such as heterosexual marriage as a case study of the complex relationship between legal and social change and of how, in keeping with Antonio Gramsci’s notion of hegemony, the dominant group in society manages agitation for change by subordinated groups while maintaining its own privilege intact.
II. The Debate
Before and after the Hawaii Supreme Court’s decision in Baehr v. Lewin, which first opened the door to extending the right to marry to same-sex couples in the United States, there was a lively debate within the LGBTQ+ community about whether marriage was a goal worth pursuing. In 1989, Thomas Stoddard and Paula Ettelbrick (both then of the Lambda Legal Defense and Education Fund) engaged in a well-known exchange on this topic, with Stoddard making arguments in favor of marriage and Ettelbrick arguing against marriage. This exchange, which is briefly recounted below, illustrates the arguments made on each side of the larger debate over whether to pursue marriage.
A. Argument for Marriage
Stoddard’s argument in favor of marriage was three-pronged. On a practical level, Stoddard accepted the privileging of marriage in American society as a given and asserted that same-sex couples should have access to the “substantial economic and practical advantages” of marriage because reproducing those advantages outside of marriage was difficult and expensive—and inherently incomplete. On a political level, Stoddard argued that marriage should be placed at the top of every LGBTQ+ rights organization’s agenda “[b]ecause marriage is . . . the political issue that most fully tests the dedication of people who are not gay to full equality for gay people, and also the issue most likely to lead ultimately to a world free from discrimination against lesbians and gay men.” Finally, on a philosophical level, Stoddard favored the “right to marry” but did not advocate that, once achieved, all lesbians and gay men ought to exercise that right. Stoddard acknowledged that “marriage may be unattractive and even oppressive as it is currently structured and practiced.” But he argued that
enlarging the concept to embrace same-sex couples would necessarily transform it into something new. . . . Extending the right to marry to gay people—that is, abolishing the traditional gender requirements of marriage—can be one of the means, perhaps the principal one, through which the institution divests itself of the sexist trappings of the past.
B. Argument Against Marriage
In contrast, Ettelbrick took a highly critical view of marriage: “Steeped in a patriarchal system that looks to ownership, property, and dominance of men over women as its basis, the institution of marriage long has been the focus of radical feminist revulsion. Marriage defines certain relationships as more valid than all others.” She saw marriage as antithetical to the “primary goals of the lesbian and gay movement.” On the one hand, Ettelbrick contended that “marriage will not liberate us as lesbians and gay men. In fact, it will constrain us, make us more invisible, force our assimilation into the mainstream, and undermine the goals of gay liberation.” On the other hand, she asserted that “attaining the right to marry will not transform our society from one that makes narrow, but dramatic, distinctions between those who are married and those who are not married to one that respects and encourages choice of relationships and family diversity.”
Ettelbrick also bristled at the constraints of legal discourse, which would require lesbians and gay men to accentuate how similar they are to heterosexuals in order to obtain marriage. She saw this rhetorical erasure of difference as the Achilles’ heel of any attempt at transforming marriage:
By looking to our sameness and de-emphasizing our differences, we don’t even place ourselves in a position of power that would allow us to transform marriage from an institution that emphasizes property and state regulation of relationships to an institution which recognizes one of many types of valid and respected relationships. Until the constitution is interpreted to respect and encourage differences, pursuing the legalization of same-sex marriage would be leading our movement into a trap; we would be demanding access to the very institution which, in its current form, would undermine our movement to recognize many different kinds of relationships.
Ettelbrick further feared that an unbending focus on “rights” would come at the expense of “justice” because obtaining the right to marry for a few “would do nothing to correct the power imbalances between those who are married . . . and those who are not.”
C. A Hindsight View
Fast-forward a quarter century and it is easy to see how this debate was resolved. Opposition to pursuing marriage grew more muted within the LGBTQ+ community while opposition from without grew more vocal and governments of all levels took steps to prevent marriage from being extended to same-sex couples. Marriage eventually became the primary focus of the LGBTQ+ movement, and public opinion began to shift, with those in favor of same-sex marriage outnumbering those against by the early 2010s. Following that shift in public opinion, the U.S. Supreme Court issued two decisions just two years apart that extended marriage to same-sex couples on constitutional grounds. The first, United States v. Windsor, required the federal government to legally recognize same-sex couples who were validly married under state law. The second, Obergefell v. Hodges, required all states to permit same-sex couples to marry. Though the legal battle for same-sex marriage was won, opponents continue to resist these judicial decisions.
In light of Stoddard’s and Ettelbrick’s (not to mention others’) sharply dissonant views regarding the transformative potential of same-sex marriage, these early years following the advent of marriage equality provide an opportunity to consider what, if any, transformative effect same-sex marriage has begun to have on American society. I explore this question by examining the Service’s reaction to the Windsor and Obergefell cases. This tax lens is enlightening both because we all pay taxes or do things that trigger or impact our taxes every day and because tax benefits were at the heart of the legal arguments for marriage equality (indeed, Windsor itself involved a federal estate tax controversy). As this Article demonstrates, the Service’s response to the legalization of same-sex marriage suggests that Ettelbrick’s concerns that the campaign for marriage equality would ultimately run counter to the LGBTQ+ movement’s goals of encouraging the affirmation of difference and the validation of choice among family structures were well founded.
III. Pre-Windsor Tax Landscape
Historically, federal tax law deferred to state law when determining who is married. For more than 80 years, this meant that same-sex relationships were not recognized for federal tax purposes because no state permitted same-sex couples to marry. Following the Hawaii Supreme Court’s decision in Baehr v. Lewin, however, Congress feared that this deference to state law might soon force the federal government to legally recognize same-sex relationships. In response, Congress enacted the Defense of Marriage Act (DOMA), which defined marriage for purposes of federal law as a union of “one man and one woman.”
As states extended legal recognition to same-sex couples, DOMA denied them access to the tax certainty that accompanies marriage, relegating them instead to a wilderness of tax uncertainty. For instance, as I have explored in detail elsewhere, married different-sex couples who pooled their income were (and still are) protected from adverse tax consequences by federal income and gift tax exemptions for transfers of property between spouses. DOMA denied same-sex couples access to these tax exemptions, but did nothing to instruct same-sex couples regarding how their intertwined financial lives would be treated for tax purposes in the absence of those exemptions. Same-sex couples had no idea which among many potential characterizations of the financial transfers between them the Service might choose on an intrusive audit. Would the Service attempt to characterize one partner’s greater contributions to the pool as payments for services, gifts, or support payments—or something else entirely? The different potential characterizations entailed different tax consequences, some of which could result in punitively taxing the same dollars multiple times.
While same-sex couples grappled with the uncertainty surrounding the tax treatment of their relationships, the Service provided helpful guidance to different-sex couples in states that permitted them to enter into marriage alternatives. With no statutory barrier to treating these different-sex couples as married for federal tax purposes, H&R Block sent an inquiry in 2011 to the Service asking whether a different-sex couple who had entered into an Illinois civil union could file a joint federal income tax return. In keeping with basic tax principles that look to substance rather than form in determining tax consequences, the Service responded that the couple could file a joint return because civil unions and marriages are legally equivalent under Illinois law. Word of this position circulated among the tax bar, and the Illinois Department of Revenue apparently relied upon it when advising different-sex civil union couples that they could file joint income tax returns at both the federal and state levels. Thus, before Windsor, there were cracks in marriage’s monopoly on relationship recognition for federal tax purposes that could only have been expected to grow once same-sex relationships were legally recognized at the federal level.
IV. Post-Windsor Surprise
Shortly following the Supreme Court’s Windsor decision, the Service issued Revenue Ruling 2013-17 to clarify which same-sex relationships would be recognized for federal tax purposes because, at that time, the majority of states still denied same-sex couples the right to marry. Revenue Ruling 2013-17 broadly recognized any same-sex marriage that was valid where celebrated, even if the couple resided in a state that refused to recognize same-sex marriages. At the same time, the Service explained that it would embrace a broad, purposive reading of the gendered terms husband and wife in the Internal Revenue Code (Code) so that those terms would include married same-sex couples. Then, at the end of that long ruling, the Service summarily stated—without any supporting legal reasoning—that it would deny legal recognition to any relationship that was “not denominated as a marriage” under state law.
At first, some thought that the Service’s position regarding marriage alternatives was simply political posturing. Because Windsor had no effect on state law (the decision merely required the federal government to revert to its historic deference to state law on questions of marital status), it was thought that denying legal recognition to civil unions and domestic partnerships might be a strategic move to pressure states that had created alternative relationship statuses to extend the right to marry to same-sex couples. Indeed, in less than a month, the Service’s position was cited in a New Jersey court decision holding that the state’s civil union law unconstitutionally denied equal treatment to same-sex couples. In that decision, the court ordered the State of New Jersey to extend the right to marry to same-sex couples.
Yet, any political impetus for denying legal recognition to marriage alternatives as a means of encouraging states to extend the right to marry to same-sex couples disappeared once the Supreme Court decided Obergefell v. Hodges, which mandated that all states extend the right to marry to same-sex couples. But any hope that the Service’s position was merely an act of political opportunism was quickly extinguished. Within a few months of Obergefell, the Treasury Department (Treasury) and the Service proposed regulations that reaffirmed the Service’s position in Revenue Ruling 2013-17.
Those regulations proposed to recognize “[a] marriage of two individuals . . . for federal tax purposes if the marriage would be recognized by any state, possession, or territory of the United States.” The regulations went on to provide that “[t]he terms spouse, husband, and wife do not include individuals who have entered into a registered domestic partnership, civil union, or other similar relationship not denominated as a marriage under the law of a state, possession, or territory of the United States.” Treasury and the Service provided three reasons for denying legal recognition to marriage alternatives: (1) states that created marriage alternatives “have intentionally chosen not to denominate those relationships as marriages,” (2) recognizing these relationships might upset the expectations of couples who entered into them to reap greater federal benefits (under Social Security, for example) than they would if they were “married,” and (3) “no provision of the Code indicates that Congress intended to recognize as marriages civil unions, registered domestic partnerships, or similar relationships.”
V. Reaction to the Proposed Regulations
Treasury and the Service received only a handful of responses to the proposed regulations—a total of a dozen individuals and organizations submitted comments. One of those comments consisted of a single sentence of religious protest: “Marriage is between one man and one woman ordained by God not the government.” Another likewise went beyond the scope of the regulations by urging Treasury and the Service to take a position regarding the application of Obergefell’s constitutional analysis to the laws of states that recognize common-law marriage. Of the comments that addressed matters within the Service’s purview, the discussion below focuses on those regarding the proposed rules relating to marriage alternatives.
A. Comments of General Support
Some comments voiced general support for the proposed regulations. A trio of labor organizations applauded Treasury and the Service for issuing guidance in the form of regulations rather than relying on the more informal (and less visible) types of guidance that it had historically used to address tax issues relevant to the LGBTQ+ community. The Family Equality Council similarly applauded Treasury and the Service, but suggested that the Service should amend its forms to use the gender-neutral term spouse rather than the terms husband and wife.
B. Neutral and Supportive Comments
Several commenters directly addressed the decision by Treasury and the Service not to recognize marriage alternatives. One commenter voiced neither support nor opposition to that decision. Instead, he merely suggested the addition of a section to the proposed regulations addressing questions faced by registered domestic partners in community property states that stem from the tension between (1) the Service’s preexisting position recognizing the application of state property law to domestic partners and (2) the intersection of the proposed regulations with Code provisions that speak to the treatment of married couples under community property regimes.
Two commenters wrote in support of the decision by Treasury and the Service not to recognize marriage alternatives. Mark Wojcik, a professor at John Marshall Law School, framed his support as respecting the choice made by couples to remain in a civil union or domestic partnership even after the advent of same-sex marriage. Wojcik’s comments made no mention, however, of the plight of couples who cannot convert their civil union or domestic partnership into a marriage (e.g., due to the death or incapacity of one of the partners or breakdown of the relationship) or of intact couples whose choice of relationship status is circumscribed by continuing fears of discrimination—subjects that were directly addressed by some of those who wrote in opposition to the proposed regulations’ treatment of marriage alternatives, as discussed below.
Stephanie Hunter McMahon, a professor at the University of Cincinnati College of Law, opened her supportive comments with a focus on section 6013(a), which authorizes joint filing of income tax returns. McMahon observed that this provision only permits “[a] husband and wife” to file a joint return. Based on the text of section 6013, McMahon argued that the Service has no authority to “overwrite the statute” and extend legal recognition to marriage alternatives because marriage alternatives are not specifically mentioned in the statute. Taken to its logical conclusion, however, that argument would also seem to preclude the Service from recognizing same-sex marriages through the proposed regulations—after all, permitting married same-sex couples to file jointly would just as clearly overwrite the statute by undoing section 6013(a)’s explicit limitation of joint filing not just to married couples but specifically to different-sex married couples (i.e., “a husband and wife”). Under McMahon’s argument, it would seem that Congress alone has the power to amend the law to comply with the spirit of the Supreme Court’s marriage equality decisions—as she says, “Extension of joint filing beyond the statute is a decision for Congress and not the Treasury Department.” Compounding the logical problems with her argument, McMahon paradoxically suggested that, before Obergefell, the Service would have been justified in recognizing marriage alternatives to afford equitable treatment to same-sex couples, even though, according to her reading of the statute, this action would be ultra vires and invalid.
McMahon further justified her support for the proposed regulations on policy grounds. She asserted that recognizing marriage alternatives would cause a drain on government resources because the Service would need to evaluate the rights and obligations of each marriage alternative to determine whether it is sufficiently equivalent to marriage. Undercutting her own point, however, McMahon made a passing reference to how the Service had previously dealt with and resolved similar issues created by the proliferation of different forms of business entities. McMahon also pointed to the potential for abuse by states colluding with their citizens to create marriage alternatives to achieve tax advantages. But in making this argument, McMahon ignored both that marriage itself has given rise to the pervasive need to police taxpayer abuse and that refusing recognition to marriage alternatives only creates new and further possibilities for abuse.
C. Comments in Opposition
Three commenters strongly opposed the decision by Treasury and the Service to refuse recognition to marriage alternatives. The Human Rights Campaign urged Treasury and the Service to recognize civil unions and domestic partnerships both because other agencies (e.g., the Social Security Administration) already recognized these relationships and because “marriage remains out of reach for many same-sex couples due to fear of discrimination.” Donald Read, a long-time tax practitioner and then-member of the IRS Advisory Council, also urged Treasury and the Service to recognize marriage alternatives. Read rejected the rationales offered by Treasury and the Service for refusing such recognition as “contrived and unpersuasive.” The ABA Section of Taxation (Tax Section) similarly described the decision by Treasury and the Service to deny legal recognition to marriage alternatives as “seriously flawed.”
With respect to the first justification proffered by Treasury and the Service (i.e., deference to state law), Read argued that “[t]he proposed regulations do not show the deference to state domestic relations law that the Preamble asserts. The proposed regulations do violence to the principles of Windsor and Obergefell. And they violate longstanding ‘cornerstone’ tax principle that substance should prevail over form.” Like Read, the Tax Section observed that Treasury and the Service were not actually deferring to the states as they purported to be doing:
The state legislatures were in most cases limited in their ability to recognize same-sex relationships either as a political matter or by a state constitutional provision that banned them from enacting legislation extending “marriage” to same-sex couples. It is also important to bear in mind that when they first appeared on the scene, civil unions and domestic partnerships were heralded as granting full equality to same-sex couples, but within a short time came to be seen as doing nothing more than relegating same-sex couples to a second-class, separate-but-equal status. With this history in mind, it becomes clear that to deny legal recognition to these relationships based on the label applied to them—especially, but not exclusively, in open years when these relationships were the only legal status available to same-sex couples—would make the Service a party to the very sort of discrimination that the U.S. Supreme Court declared unconstitutional in Obergefell and Windsor and that the Service is attempting to remedy through the Proposed Regulations.
The Tax Section argued that, “[t]o truly defer to the states, the Service should ignore the labels applied to these alternative relationships and be guided instead by their legal equivalence to marriage under state law in determining their federal tax treatment.”
With respect to the second justification proffered by Treasury and the Service (i.e., frustrated expectations of couples in marriage alternatives), Read explained that this justification was nothing more than a red herring. Before the Supreme Court’s same-sex marriage decisions, the only couples who had a choice between marriage and a civil union or domestic partnership were different-sex couples—the same-sex couples for whom these alternatives were originally designed had little or no choice among relationship statuses. The Tax Section further noted that, even after the Supreme Court decisions, some same-sex couples remained trapped in alternative relationships and unable to marry because of the death or incapacity of one of the partners—and the same is, of course, true for those whose relationships broke down before marriage became available but who did not split until afterward. These couples never had a real “choice” among relationship statuses that Treasury and the Service would be honoring—their only choice was between a marriage alternative or no legal recognition at all. Compounding the disregard for couples still suffering the legacy of unconstitutional discrimination, the Tax Section pointed out that the actual expectation of all couples in civil unions and domestic partnerships prior to 2013 was—based on the Service’s own informal guidance—that these relationships would be recognized for federal tax purposes. If anything, it was the Service’s post-Windsor change in position that frustrated taxpayer expectations.
Furthermore, both Read and the Tax Section opposed the idea that interpretation of the tax laws should be dictated by couples’ expectations regarding the tax and nontax benefits that they might achieve through abusive behavior that takes advantage of gaps in the law. The Tax Section noted that the tax law doctrine of substance over form was designed precisely to combat such behavior and also noted that setting tax policy in order to influence Social Security or other federal benefits is outside the purview of Treasury and the Service. And, as Read remarked, “it is not clear that their device works—Social Security bases spousal status for benefits on whether one person would take from the other under intestacy laws, which, in California, registered domestic partners clearly do.”
With respect to the final justification proffered by Treasury and the Service (i.e., that Congress had not enacted a provision recognizing marriage alternatives), both Read and the Tax Section underscored how untenable this argument was, with the Tax Section explaining:
[U]ntil the Windsor decision, Congress refused to treat even married same-sex couples as spouses for federal tax purposes. It is implausible to expect that Congress would have enacted a provision indicating that if the federal Defense of Marriage Act were ever struck down, only married spouses and not registered domestic partners or parties to a civil union could be treated as married. Moreover, the lack of a specific provision in the Code addressing the exact situation faced by a taxpayer has never been a barrier to the application of the principle of substance over form; indeed, the inability of Congress to timely address every situation faced by taxpayers is the raison d’être of that principle.
The Tax Section concluded its comments by noting that the proposed rule regarding the recognition of marriage was inconsistent with the proposed regulations’ position regarding marriage alternatives. The proposed regulations would recognize a marriage so long as any state, possession, or territory would recognize the relationship as a marriage. As the Tax Section observed, some states already recognized as a marriage not only civil unions and domestic partnerships but any relationship that has “substantially” the same rights and obligations as a marriage. Thus, despite purporting to deny recognition to marriage alternatives, the proposed rule for determining marital status actually would require the Service to recognize marriage alternatives because at least one state already classified them as marriages under its laws.