chevron-down Created with Sketch Beta.

Real Property, Trust and Estate Law Journal

Summer 2024

Power Tools For Choice Of Law On Trust Validity

James P Spica

Summary

  • States have important policy reasons for regulating domestic settlors’ freedom to designate foreign state law to govern trust validity. 
  • This Article reveals how fundamentally such regulation depends on the state’s having a compatible choice-of-law rule on the validity of exercises of trust-spawned special powers of appointment. 
  • The Article develops a black-letter version of the needful validity-of-exercise rule that picks up where the Restatement (Second) of Conflict of Laws’ version of the rule leaves off.
Power Tools For Choice Of Law On Trust Validity
MirageC via Getty Images

Jump to:

I. Introduction

Issue characterization is more or less fundamental to the choice-of-law process. That makes classification a prominent feature of any systematic presentation of the rules of private international law or conflict of laws. One has only to look, for example, at the Table of Contents of the Restatement (Second) of Conflict of Laws (Restatement of Conflicts), to see how neatly the taxonomic divisions and subdivisions of one very influential exposition of choice-of-law rules map on the analytical categories—civil procedure, evidence, torts, contracts, commercial transactions, property, and so on—that inform a traditional law school curriculum.

To some extent, the selection and order of analytical categories in a treatise like the Restatement of Conflicts will be a matter of expository convenience, like deciding which rules for operations with numbers to assume and which to prove in the presentation of a mathematical treatise. But the use of purely theoretical categories is liable to obscure informative organic affinities between categorically distinct legal concepts or relations. “The creation of characterization categories [for conflicts purposes] is to some extent an artificial process, an attempt to impose order on a market of conflicting legal rules and tending, unless care is taken, to be rigid and blinkered.”

II. The Choice-of-Law Specific Organic Affinity of Trusts and Special Powers of Appointment

We might try, for example, to classify the rules of “conflict of laws in trusts and estates” hierarchically based on their applications to the special jural relations that inhabit the field of trusts and estates law. In that case, choice-of-law rules on the validity of trust-spawned special powers of appointment and the validity of exercises of such powers would be hived off from choice-of-law rules on the validity of express trusts. For though they are symbiotic (a trustee’s discretionary distribution power, for example, is a special power of appointment), trusts and powers are distinct legal relations. The doneesof expressly fiduciary powers of appointment, for example, are often not trustees. And unlike the beneficiaries of a trust in respect of the res, “the objects of [a] power, qua objects, will not be entitled to any share of or interest in the subject-matter of the power” unless and until the power is exercised.

The tendency of powers and trusts to interbreed in the wild, the frequency, that is, with which trusts are created by exercises of trust-spawned fiduciary and nonfiduciary special powers of appointment, would no doubt tend to embarrass a hierarchical presentation. It would be inelegant, for example, if by treating express trusts and powers of appointment as genetic cousins for choice-of-law purposes (rather than parents, children, and siblings), we should end up (1) enshrining the pedestrian proposition that the validity of a power of appointment granted by the terms of a trust is determined by the law that determines the validity of the trust in “black letter” while (2) leaving the corresponding propositions regarding equitable interests and nondispositive fiduciary administrative powers to be inferred.

But whatever the symbiosis of powers and trusts may indicate for the presentation of a scheme of conflicts rules, it has an imperative effect on the content of such a scheme. That is because (as we are about to see) unless a given state is constitutionally laissez-faire about what domestic settlors can do with express trusts, the state is bound to regulate choice of law on the validity of such trusts, and it cannot regulate choice of law on the validity of express trusts without compatibly regulating choice of law on the validity of exercises of trust-spawned special powers of appointment.

III. Necessity

A. Local Law Restrictions on Express Trusts Necessitate Trust-Validity, Choice-of-Law Restrictions on Settlor Autonomy

Every state has to regulate what settlors can do with express trusts: a state that has even one public policy cannot countenance, for example, a purpose trust for the encouragement of domestic behavior in violation of that policy (whatever it is). And the possibility that states will espouse different policies entails a risk of conflicts requiring choice of law. Thus, a state that wants to regulate what domestic settlors can do with express trusts in any particular respect in which another state is, or may be, more relaxed is bound to add settlors’ ability to determine the choice of law on trust validity to the list of things it wants to regulate. Otherwise, the state’s choice-of-law rules are liable to make its local law limitations on express trusts elective.

1. Risk of Policy Evasion

Of course, some of the things settlors can do to determine the law governing trust validity will be unobjectionable from a regulating state’s point of view. Before creating a trust t, for example, the intending settlor of t might resolutely change her dwelling place and “the center of [her] domestic, social, and civil life” from somewhere in Regulating State to a place in Relaxed State, thus making Relaxed State her home. In combination with other facts, such a move will cause Regulating State to acknowledge that as matter of policy, the application of its own local law on a particular issue involving t would be unreasonable given the relationship of t to Relaxed State (or some other state). Unreasonable because in a multi-state system, each state is motivated to determine applicable law, on a given issue, in a given matter, by weighting “policy factors” that will include (what might be termed) “the relative interests of [interested] states in the determination of the particular issue.” The relative interests of states will be based on the distribution of “connecting factors” by virtue of which a given state may be said to be interested. And in a case involving an express trust, the connecting factors will presumably include the domicile of the settlor at the time the trust is created.

So, what Regulating State is bound to add to the list of things it wants to regulate is not settlors’ ability to determine the choice of law on trust validity generally. Rather it is settlors’ ability to direct the choice of law away from Regulating State when Regulating State is the state to which the trust in question has (what might be termed) its “most significant relationship as to the matter at issue as indicated by the relevant policy factors (PF-Set) given the distribution of connecting factors (CF-Set) among implicated states. In other words, what Regulating State rationally wants to avoid is a situation in which the settlor of a trust t eludes Regulating State’s local-law restrictions on a matter m (whatever it is) by arranging for the law of Relaxed State to govern the validity of t when Regulating State is the state to which t has its most significant relationship as to m based on the relative interests of interested states.

2. A First Case in Point

That situation will certainly be possible if the settlor of t is allowed simply to designate, in the terms of t, the state whose law will govern the validity of t. Suppose, for example, that the local law of Regulating State provides a surviving spouse a statutory forced share of a deceased spouse’s “augmented estate,” whereas the local law of Relaxed State exempts assets transferred in trust from forced-share rules. If we also suppose that Relaxed State sanctions self-settled trusts and that Regulating State’s conflicts rules allow settlors to designate state law to govern trust validity, a settlor, S, who is domiciled in Regulating State, might seek to disinherit her spouse by creating an irrevocable trust t, retaining the rights to receive trust income and to direct trust investments, and expressly providing that t’s validity is to be determined under the local law of Relaxed State.

3. The Needful Settlor-Autonomy-Constraining, Choice-of-Law Rule on Trust Validity

Whether states should recognize settlors’ designations of state law to govern trust validity at all is debatable. But states commonly do, subject to limitations, and we shall assume hereafter that Regulating State does likewise. But in that case, to disarm the threat of policy evasion posed by our first case in point, Regulating State will enact or judicially recognize a choice-of-law rule according to which a settlor’s designation of state law to govern the validity of a trust will be respected only if the state designated has (as it might be expressed) “a substantial relation to the trust and . . . the application of [that state’s] law does not violate a strong public policy of the state with which, as to the matter at issue, the trust has its most significant relationship.” For this purpose, the substantiality of a state’s relation to the trust will be determined by the state’s implication in any of the factors in the CF-Set, and the relative significance of a state’s relationship to the trust as to the matter at issue will be determined under the PF-Set in light of the CF-Set array.

These constraints on settlor autonomy—the substantial-relation requirement and public-policy override (Settlor Autonomy Constraints)—will be associated with a trust-validity default rule for cases in which the settlor either fails to make a designation or makes one that violates one of the Settlor Autonomy Constraints. The policy-override dictates that a congruous default designation will either itself have the same policy-override or will simply supply as the default designation, the description (as it may be expressed) “the state with which, as to the matter at issue, the trust has its most significant relationship.”

We should note that the confluence of the Settlor Autonomy Constraints and the trust-validity default rule just described entails that talk about “the law which determines the validity of [a given] trust” is loose. For a trust is “valid” (if it is) under that confluence (Validity of Trust Rule) “as to [a given] matter at issue.” And we are not to suppose “that all questions of validity will be determined by the same law”: “What state has the most significant relationship with the trust [in question] may depend upon the particular ground of invalidity.” So, under the Validity of Trust Rule, an assertion of the general validity of a given trust or its provisions has to be unpacked in terms of the absences of “particular ground[s] of invalidity.” According to this analytical litotes, the terms of a trust t are valid (if they are) because they are not invalid in respect of the RAP under the law of the state that has the most significant relationship with t as to remoteness of vesting, because they are not invalid in respect of the rule against accumulation of income under the law of the state that has the most significant relationship with t as to accumulations, because they are not invalid in respect of formalities under the law of the state that has the most significant relationship with t as to formalities, and so on.

B. Trust-Validity, Choice-of-Law Restrictions on Settlor Autonomy Require Congruous Choice-of-Law Restrictions on the Validity of Exercises of Trust-Spawned Special Powers

The particular ground of invalidity implicated in our first case in point is S’s trust t’s effect on S’s augmented estate. And we may assume that Regulating State has the most significant relationship with t as to disinheritance of S’s spouse. That means that under the Validity of Trust Rule, Regulating State’s interest in the determination of the effect of t on S’s augmented estate will outweigh that of Relaxed State, S’s designation of Relaxed State in t’s governing law provision notwithstanding. But S has another string to her bow unless Regulating State’s Validity of Trust Rule is supported by a congruous choice-of-law rule on the validity of exercises of trust-spawned special powers of appointment.

1. An Independent Risk of Policy Evasion

To see this, we need only assume temporarily that Regulating State has enacted section 103(2) of the Uniform Powers of Appointment Act (UPAA). UPAA section 103(2) provides that “[u]nless the terms of the instrument creating a power of appointment manifest a contrary intent[,] the exercise . . . of the power . . . is governed by the law of the powerholder’s domicile at the relevant time.” One of the questions to be “governed” by the law governing the exercise of a power of appointment is the validity of whatever dispositive arrangement the exercise purports to effect. Thus, when a trust t2 is created by the exercise of a special power of appointment granted under the terms of a (different) trust t1, the state law that governs the validity of the exercise (according to the applicable choice-of-law rule) determines the validity of t2. What UPAA section 103(2) tells us about such a case is that the state law that governs the validity of the exercise and, therefore, determines the validity of t2, is the law of the domicile of the donee of the special power, regardless of what state law determines the validity of t1.

2. Special-Power Elaboration of Our First Case in Point

Since by hypothesis, Regulating State has enacted UPAA section 103(2), all S has to do is grant someone domiciled in Relaxed State—either directly, that is, nominatim, or through the offices of a “trust protector”—a special power of appointment (that is valid as such according to Regulating State’s law) to transfer the assets of t in trust subject to the same administrative and dispositive terms as those of t (omitting, perhaps, the terms pertaining to the special power itself) for the benefit of the same beneficiaries as those of t. In that case, the donee’s exercise of the special power will itself make Regulating State’s augmented-estate regime irrelevant, as far as Regulating State is concerned, to the t-mimic trust that results. And the donee’s exercise will do that without in any way altering S’s dispositive arrangement.

This is surely too easy. But on our assumed facts, it works. There is no question of a so-called “fraud on [the] power” here. For the donee will have exercised the t-spawned special power in exactly the way S intended, which excludes the possibility of “an ulterior purpose.” And S’s own conditions on the exercise of the power exclude the possibility of the donee’s impermissibly benefiting an impermissible object. The donor of a power of appointment is free to place extensive, highly detailed conditions on the exercise of a power:

questions as to the kind of power created, its scope, and the duties and obligations (if any) which are attached to it or to its exercise, are generally determined by process of ascertaining what the creator of that power intended . . . . Within the limits and requirements of the law, his intentions tend to predominate and prevail (but he cannot, for example contravene public policy, such as the rule against perpetuities, or ignore requirements of certainty).

And it can hardly be argued that the power in question contravenes public policy when it is Regulating State’s enactment of UPAA section 103(2) that does S’s bidding. By that enactment, Regulating State has said that the law of the domicile of the donee of the t-spawned power should determine the validity of the dispositive arrangement that S has authorized the donee to effect.

A judge might rightly observe that Regulating State’s choice-of-laws rules (on the assumptions of our special-power-elaborated first case in point) are incoherent. But she will not therefore feel free, in applying Regulating State’s law, to disregard or improve the State’s enactment of UPAA section 103(2). “The power to add to, alter or ignore statutory words is an extremely limited one. Generally speaking, it can only be exercised where there has been a demonstrable mistake on the part of the drafter.” Even if the Validity of Trust Rule (with its Settlor Autonomy Constraints) is codified, and that codification predates the State’s enactment of section 103(2), the judge is not likely to say that when a trust is created by the exercise of a trust-spawned special power of appointment, the Validity of Trust Rule is, as far as Regulating State is concerned, the more specific of the two choice-of-law statutes for purposes of the canon generalia specialibus non derogant. For the Validity of Trust Rule expressly says no more about powers of appointment than section 103(2) expressly says about trusts.

And in any case, the legislative history—that is, the Uniform Law Commission (ULC) Comment to UPAA section 103(2)—suggests that the incoherence in question must have been “intentional” because section 103(2) is avowedly meant to be “a departure from [the principle that] the law of the donor’s domicile governs acts both of the donor (such as the creation of the power) and of the powerholder (such as the exercise of the power).” So, our temporary assumption that Regulating State has enacted UPAA section 103(2) yields that, as far as Regulating State is concerned, S’s status as the settlor of t is irrelevant to the choice of law on the validity of the t-mimic trust created by exercise of the t-spawned special power of appointment in our special-power-elaborated first case in point. All that matters for that purpose under section 103(2) is the domicile (which we have set in Relaxed State) of the donee of the t-spawned special power.

3. Rejecting UPAA Section 103(2) en Route to the Needful Validity-of-Exercise Choice-of-Law Rule

It is difficult to imagine why Regulating State would knowingly adopt a choice-of-law rule on the validity of exercises of trust-spawned powers of appointment that could so easily be used to subvert its attempts to regulate the disinheritance of spouses, remoteness of vesting, accumulation of income, the performance of noncharitable purpose trusts, the exculpation of trustees and other trust fiduciaries, the enforceability of spendthrift provisions in self-settled trusts, settlors’ ability to waive notice of trust existence for beneficiaries . . . any regulated activity pertinent to express trusts to which some other state turns, or might turn, a blind eye. By making a mere connecting factor—viz., “the powerholder’s domicile at the relevant time”determinative of choice of law without an override for a strong public policy of the state with which, as to the matter at issue, the trust has its most significant relationship, UPAA section 103(2) commends the special power of appointment to a determined settlor as a means of throwing off the Settlor Autonomy Constraints in choosing law to govern trust validity.

So, to the extent a state like Regulating State understands its motivation to adhere to the Settlor Autonomy Constraints of the Validity of Trust Rule, it is bound to reject a validity-of-exercise, choice-of-law rule like UPAA section 103(2). To that extent, it will prefer some alternative that vindicates the intuitive ideas (1) that for policy purposes, the donee of the t-spawned special power in our special-power-elaborated first case in point is effectively acting merely as S’s agent and (2) that a settlor ought not to be able to achieve trust objectives that are otherwise prohibited by applicable local law simply by interposing a special power of appointment.

IV. Functionality

A. A First Approximation of the Needful Validity-of-Exercise, Choice-of-Law Rule

On the simple facts of our special-power-elaborated first case in point, the choice-of-law rule described in section 274(a) of the Restatement of Conflicts foots the bill. Section 274(a) provides that when a special power to appoint movables is granted under the terms of a trust, the substantial validity of a dispositive arrangement created by an exercise of the power—that is, the substantial validity of an attempted appointment—is determined “in accordance with the law which determines the validity of the [special-power-spawning] trust.” Under that rule, when a trust t2 is created by the exercise of a special power of appointment (over movables) granted under the terms of a trust t1, the validity of t2 is determined by the law that determines the validity of t1. And that is true regardless of the designation (if any) of governing law in the t2 trust instrument.

Now, we know that by “in accordance with the law which determines the validity of the [special-power-spawning] trust,” Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) means in accordance with the law which determines the validity of the special-power-spawning trust as to the matter at issue. We know that questions concerning the validity of a given trust are individuated by “particular ground[s] of invalidity.” And we know that the particular ground of invalidity implicated in our special-power-elaborated first case in point is the same as that implicated in the unelaborated first case in point, viz., the effect on S’s augmented estate for purposes of Regulating State’s forced share rule. For we know that except perhaps for the terms of trust t that pertain to the t-spawned special power itself, the administrative and dispositive provisions of the t-mimic trust are identical to those of t and are for the benefit of the same beneficiaries.

Under the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a), then, the validity of the t-mimic trust (as the intended result of the exercise of the t-spawned special power) as to the matter of its effect on S’s augmented estate would be determined in accordance with the law that determines the validity of trust t as to that matter. We have assumed that under the Settlor Autonomy Constraints of the Validity of Trust Rule, Regulating State’s interest in determining t’s effect on S’s augmented estate would outweigh that of Relaxed State even if S should expressly designate Relaxed State’s law to govern trust validity. So, the law that determines the validity of t as to its effect on S’s augmented estate would be the law of Regulating State. And that would be true regardless of the designation (if any) of governing law in the t-mimic trust instrument. So, the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 724(a) would prevent S form circumventing the policy override of the Validity of Trust Rule’s Settlor Autonomy Constraints. And we thus have our vindication of the intuitive principle that on the facts of our special-power-elaborated first case in point, S ought not to be able to achieve trust objectives that are otherwise prohibited by the local law of Regulating State simply by interposing a special power of appointment.

B. The Virtue of Analogy to Local Law

1. As Legal Reasoning in General

The rule of section 274(a) can be viewed as vindicating that intuitive principle—that is, that S ought not to be able to achieve trust objectives that are otherwise prohibited by the local law of Regulating State simply by interposing a special power—precisely by enforcing the concomitant intuitive principle we mentioned, that for policy purposes, the donee of the t-spawned special power of appointment in our special-power-elaborated first case in point is merely acting as S’s agent. It can be viewed in that way because the rule of section 274(a) is readily assimilated to evidence in the local law of states generally for the common law “relation back theory” of powers. And that evidence (that is, each instantiation of the theory in a decided case) is plausibly characterized as treating the donor of a special power of appointment as the author of the donee’s exercise.

It is frequently said that the property which passes upon the exercise of a power of appointment is the property of the donor and not the property of the donee of the power. It is said that the instrument by which the power is exercised is to be read back into the instrument which created the power. For this reason it is said that the substantial validity of the exercise of the power is determined by the law which determines the validity of the trust under which the power was created.

This is undoubtedly so where the power is a special power, that is, a power to appoint among a limited class of persons. The appointees take the property from the donor rather than from the donee, even though the donee may select which members of the class shall take and in what proportions. If an appointment is made in trust and the trust fails there is a resulting trust to the estate of the donor and not to the estate of the donee. See Restatement of Trusts (Second), § 427. The permissible period under the rule against perpetuities begins at the time of the creation of the power and not at the time of its exercise. See 4 Restatement of Property § 273, Comment d. The applicable law is that which governs the validity of the trust and not that which would govern a disposition by the donee of his own property.

In fact, the analogy to the resulting-trusts and perpetuities instantiations of the relation back is the only express rationale that the Restatement of Conflicts provides for the rule of section 274(a).

The resulting-trusts instantiation is arguably no more than a reiteration of the legal-taxonomic distinction between special and general powers of appointment in the particular context of a failed appointment in further trust. But the perpetuities instantiation is, indeed, integral to a state’s determination to regulate remoteness of vesting in very much the same way the desiderated validity-of-exercise choice-of-law rule is integral to a state’s determination to limit (by means of the Settlor Autonomy Constraints) settlors’ freedom to designate state law to govern trust validity. And in the perpetuities instantiation too, the risk is policy evasion by means of the interposition of a special power. The risk in the perpetuities instantiation is that the exercise of a special power of appointment will allow the vesting of future interests in assets subject to the power to be postponed for longer than the donor of the power could have arranged without interposing the power.

To prevent that, the perpetuities instantiation of the relation back theory requires that the period during which the exercise of a special power of appointment can postpone the vesting of future interests is measured from the time the power was created. “Where an appointment is made under a special power, the appointment is read back into the instrument creating the power (as if the donee were filling in blanks in the donor’s instrument) and the period of perpetuities is computed from the date the power was created.” Thus, by treating the donor of a special power—rather than the donee—as the transferor of property subject to the power, the relation back theory prevents the donee from setting a must-vest-by date of a remoteness that would have been prohibited to the donor by the RAP. Why should the theory not likewise prevent the donee of a trust-spawned special power from effecting a choice of law on trust validity that would have been prohibited to the settlor-donor of the power by the Settlor Autonomy Constraints?

2. As Reasoning about Jurisdiction-Selecting Choice of Law in Particular

a. Formal Justice

Of course, the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) (or any other choice-of-law rule) is not sufficiently commended to Regulating State (or any other state) simply by its pointing to that state’s local law on the facts of our special-power-elaborated first case in point (or any other particular situation). For a state’s motivation to treat like cases alike, a commitment, that is, to formal justice, will require the rule’s application—when applicable—whether it points to the lex fori or away:

[A] court [for example] is seeking a [choice-of-law] rule which, if it already has the pedigree of precedent, may have arisen in a case where the competing domestic laws were, with relation to the facts of the transaction, the reverse of those now before it. Moreover, the court must contemplate the use of its decision in the instant case as a precedent for the decision of some subsequent . . . case which will present still another pattern of local laws.

But as we have already noted, Regulating State’s rational policy is that when a choice of law on trust validity is in question, the State’s own substantive law should apply imperatively only when Regulating State is the state to which the trust in question has its most significant relationship as to the matter at issue. And it is on that basis that the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) is commended to Regulating State (or any other state) on the facts of our special-power-elaborated first case in point. The rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) locates the rule of decision on the validity of the t-mimic trust (as the intended result of the exercise of the t-spawned special power) by pointing to the state whose law determines the validity of t, and the Validity of Trust Rule—either by its default designation or the policy override of the Settlor Autonomy Constraints—points to Regulating State to provide the rule of decision on the validity of t because Regulating State is the state to which t has its most significant relationship as to the effect of t on S’s augmented estate.

b. Substantive Justice

Thus, Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) and its confluence with the Validity of Trust Rule are entirely consistent with Regulating State’s commitment to formal justice. But formal justice, “[t]reating similar cases similarly[,] is not a sufficient guarantee of substantive justice.” And as the preceding discussion emphasizes, the operative effect of section 274(a)’s conjunction with the Validity of Trust Rule is jurisdiction selection: the conjunction points directly, not to a rule of decision (on the validity of an exercise of a trust-spawned special power of appointment), but to a state, “a territorial unit having a distinct general body of law,” regardless of the content of any of rules comprised by that body of law.

When a case arises in which a foreign law is offered in evidence or in which the applicability of the law of the forum is denied, a court faithful to the conventional approach will turn in search of a conflict of laws rule to determine the jurisdiction whose law should govern the question at issue. The conflicts rule indicates in which jurisdiction the appropriate law may be found. Assuming the law offered to be from that jurisdiction, the court will then proceed with the case, employing that law as a rule of decision. Not until its admission for that purpose does the content of that law become material.

And that raises a profoundly simple question: How can a litigant who but for the “foreign element” in her case would be entitled to demand justice according to the local law of the forum, be relegated by the forum to a rule of decision selected without regard to the rule’s content and, therefore, without regard to its effect upon the litigant’s claim? “The court is [after all,] not idly choosing a law; it is determining a controversy. How can it choose wisely without considering how that choice will affect that controversy?” This is a question of substantive justice. And the prospect of Justice’s being blind to substance is philosophically unsettling; for it seems to invite the criticism that

instead of declaring an overriding public policy, [a jurisdiction-selecting, choice-of-law rule] proclaims the state’s indifference to the result of the litigation. Let there be a domestic case of [for example] tort or contract, and the law of the state points to the result which alone can advance the social and economic policy embodied in that law. Let a conventionally suitable foreign factor be injected and the state immediately loses interest.

But that criticism is avoided (or blunted) to the extent that a jurisdiction-selecting, choice-of-law rule can be derived by analogy to local law. It is therefore significant that the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) can be derived or explained by the ordinary method of common law argument and justification, viz., analogy and distinction, from local law evidence for a “general theoretical proposition[] of the common law,” viz., the relation back theory. To that extent, the forum discerns in its own local law, by the ordinary method of common law elaboration, a reason to look away for a rule of decision and to do so without regard to the content of the desiderated rule. The forum’s reaction to the hypothesized litigant’s case is not a knee-jerk at its “foreign element” but a standard evaluation of its substance. Hence in a conflicts scheme whose choice-of-law rules are generally jurisdiction-selecting, a choice-of-law rule that can be derived or supported by analogical reasoning from the local law of the forum is charmed. And the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) has that charm.

C. The Vice of Rough Analogy (and Herein of Interpretation)

But charming as the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) is in theory, it is liable to be awkward in practice; for the rule’s being derivable by analogy from local law—the very feature that gives it its charm in theory—threatens to make heavy weather of cases that, unlike our special-power-elaborated first case in point, involve a succession of successively generated trust-spawned special powers.

1. A Second Case in Point

Let us suppose that by a transfer of assets that she owned outright (or over which she held, at the time, a presently exercisable general power of appointment), a settlor, S, settled an irrevocable inter vivos trust, t1. T1’s “governing law” provision (concerning validity as well as construction and administration) designated the law of State A. And t1’s dispositive terms granted a beneficiary, D1, who was domiciled in (different) State B, a special power, p1, to appoint the trust assets (which were movables). The dispositive arrangement effected by D1’s exercise of p1 was a trust, t2, whose governing law provision (including validity) designated the law of State B and under whose terms a beneficiary, D2, who was domiciled in (yet different) State C, was granted a special power, p2, over the trust assets (still movables). The dispositive arrangement effected by D2’s exercise of p2 was a trust, t3, whose governing law provision (including validity) designated the law of State C and under whose terms a beneficiary, D3, who was domiciled in (possibly different) State D, was granted a special power, p3, over the trust assets (still movables) . . . . And the dispositive arrangement effected by Dn-1’s exercise of pn-1 is a trust, tn, whose governing law provision (including validity) designates the law of State N (which is different from State A but not necessarily different from every state in the series State B, State C, State D . . . State N-1).

The problem, let us say, is that tn is an “accumulation trust,” and a beneficiary of tn, B, has petitioned a court in State N for an order striking the lengthy accumulation period prescribed by the trust’s terms on the ground that the period violates the common law rule against accumulation of income. By the time of Dn-1’s exercise of pn-1 to create tn, States N, N-1, and all of the other states in the series State B, State C, State D . . . had abrogated the common law rule against accumulation of income, though that rule remains in full vigor in State A. The only factors of the CF-Set adverting to State A are the historical facts that S executed the t1 trust instrument in State A and designated State A in the t1 trust instrument’s governing law provision. It turns out (we shall suppose) that in making that designation, S, who was then domiciled in a state that had already abrogated the common law rule against accumulation of income, had acceded to the request of a commercial trustee organized under the laws of State A that she include in the t1 instrument certain “boilerplate” designating that state’s law to govern validity. And the corporate trustee that made that request is no longer involved in the administration of any of the trusts in the series t1, t2, t3 . . . tn, only the last of which still exists.

2. A Naïve Reading

To the extent State N’s superior courts adhere to the rule of section 274(a) and treat the Restatement of Conflicts as authority for doing so, the judge hearing B’s petition in our second case in point might focus initially on the law that determines the validity of trust tn-1. According to the black letter of section 274(a), the substantial validity of tn (as the intended result of the exercise of the tn-1-spawned special power pn-1) is determined “in accordance with the law which determines the validity of the [special-power-spawning] trust.” And according to the Comments, that is true regardless of Dn-1’s designation of State N in tn’s governing law provision. Well, the pn-1-spawning trust is presumably tn-1.

Again, we know that by “in accordance with the law which determines the validity of [tn-1],” section 274(a) means in accordance with the law which determines the validity of tn-1 as to the “particular ground of invalidity” at issue. And the particular ground of invalidity at issue in our second case in point is the rule against accumulation of income. So, the question posed under section 274(a) by B’s petition might initially seem to be whether Dn-2’s designation of State N-1 in tn-1’s governing law provision violates a strong public policy of the state with which, as to accumulation of income, tn-1 has its most significant relationship. If it does not violate such a policy, that designation will be respected (according to the Validity of Trust Rule). And in that case, the question might seem (according to section 274(a)) to be just whether tn’s accumulation period is permitted under the law of State N-1—which we know to have abrogated the rule against accumulations.

We know that State A has not abrogated that rule but we also know that the only factors of the CF-Set adverting to State A are the historical facts that S executed the t1 trust instrument in State A and designated State A in the t1 instrument’s governing law provision. It may be doubted, therefore, whether State A is the state with which trust tn-1 has its most significant relationship as to any matter. And all of the other states implicated in the CF-Set have abrogated the rule against accumulations. So, the judge hearing B’s petition will have to conclude that Dn-2’s designation of State N-1 in tn-1’s governing law provision does not violate a strong public policy of the state (whichever it is) with which, as to accumulation of income, tn-1 has its most significant relationship. On this simple reading of section 274(a), that conclusion would make State N-1’s abrogation of the rule against accumulations determinative.

3. Transitivity

But B will insist that the simple reading of section 274(a) is contrary to analogy. She will emphasize that (as we have seen) the Restatement of Conflicts’ express rationale for the rule of section 274(a) is just the analogy to the resulting-trusts and perpetuities instantiations of the relation back theory. For in both of those instantiations, the relation back is transitive over successively generated special powers of appointment. As with the resulting-trusts instantiation itself, the transitivity of the relation back in that instantiation is arguably no more than a reiteration of the legal-taxonomic distinction between special and general powers of appointment in the context of a failed appointment in further trust. But the transitivity of the relation back over special powers for perpetuities purposes is nontrivial:

If [a] trust or other donative disposition was created by the exercise of a nongeneral or testamentary power that was created by the exercise of a nongeneral or a testamentary power, the relation-back doctrine is applied twice and the donor of the first power is the transferor of the trust or other donative disposition created by the second donee’s exercise of his or her power.

That means that no matter how large the number n in the hypothesized series of special powers p1, p2, p3 . . . pn-1 is, we know that pn-1 is deemed to have been “created,” for perpetuities purposes, on the date that p1 was created because according to the relation back theory, pn-1 was created when pn-2 was created, and pn-2 was created when pn-3 was created, and pn-3 was created when pn-4 was created, and so on back to the creation of pn-x = p1.

If special powers relate back (B’s argument continues) for choice-of-law purposes because they relate back in the resulting-trusts and perpetuities instantiations, and the relation back of special powers is transitive in those instantiations, then presumably the relation back is transitive for choice-of-law purposes. And since the rule of section 274(a) takes precedence in determining the substantial validity of trust tn (as the intended result of Dn-1’s exercise of pn-1) over Dn-1’s privilege as the settlor of tn to designate governing law, it likewise takes precedence over the like privilege of Dn-2 as the settlor of tn-1, that of Dn-3 as the settlor of tn-2, that of Dn-4 as the settlor of tn-3, and so on.

So (B will conclude), no matter how large the number n is, the validity of tn (as the intended result of Dn-1’s exercise of the tn-1-spawnded special power pn-1) is determined, according to the rule of section 274(a), by the law that determines the validity of t1. For the validity of tn (as such) is determined by the law that determines the validity of tn-1, the validity of tn-1 (as the intended result of Dn-2’s exercise of the tn-2-spawnded special power pn-2) is determined by the law that determines the validity of tn-2, the validity of tn-2 (as the intended result of Dn-3’s exercise of the tn-3-spawnded special power pn-3) is determined by the law that determines the validity of tn-3, and so on back to the law that determines the validity of tn-x = t1. On B’s reading of section 274(a), the question posed by B’s petition is whether S’s designation of State A in trust t1’s governing law provision violates a strong public policy of the state with which, as to accumulation of income, t1 has its most significant relationship. If it does not violate such a policy, that designation will be respected (according to the Validity of Trust Rule). And in that case, the question (according to section 274(a)) is just whether tn’s accumulation period is permitted under the law of State A—and we know that State A still enforces the common law rule against accumulations.

4. Afterlife of Special-Power-Spawning Trusts as to Particular Matters at Issue

Of course, B’s argument does not change the CF-Set array: trust t1 no longer exists, and what is left of it, that is, the fund that was once held by t1’s trustee(s) is now the res of tn, having changed fiduciary hands and “vestments,” perhaps many times (in the series t1, t2, t3 . . . tn). Thus, the sense in which t1 can be said to have a significant relationship as to accumulation of income to any state is strained. But S’s designation of the law of State A to govern the validity of t1 cannot possibly have violated a strong public policy as to accumulation of income of any of the states represented in the CF-Set; for all of the represented states other than State A permit accumulations, and that is presumably, not because any of them wishes actively to promote accumulation of income, but rather for lack of a strong public policy going the other way. Indeed, the Restatement of Conflicts assumes such a lack:

If the provision is valid under the local law of the state designated by the testator or under the local law of the place of administration, it will be held to be valid if it does not contravene a strong policy of the state of the testator's domicil. No such strong policy is involved in rules against perpetuities or rules against accumulations or rules as to indefiniteness of beneficiaries.

The latter statement—that no strong policy is involved in RAPs, rules against accumulations, or rules as to indefiniteness of beneficiaries—is no longer credible (assuming it was credible when the Restatement of Conflicts was drafted) with regard to a state that wants to enforce any of the rules mentioned. But the many states that have thrown off such rules have not done so because they wish to discourage the vesting of transferred future interests within the testing period of the common law RAP, or regular distributions of trust income, or the creation of trusts for the benefit of definite or definitely ascertainable beneficiaries. A state’s abrogation of a rule against remoteness of vesting, accumulation of income, or noncharitable purpose trusts represents a recognition, not of strong public policy, but of the absence of such a policy.

So, the long road on which the judge hearing B’s petition was set by B’s reading of section 274(a) ends in the conclusion that S’s designation of State A in t1’s governing law provision does not violate a strong public policy of the state (whichever it is) with which, as to accumulation of income, t1 has (in whatever sense it can be said to have) its most significant relationship. It follows that State A’s adherence to the rule against accumulations is determinative (on the question of the validity of tn and its initial accumulation period).

5. Embarrassment

By hypothesis, State N’s superior courts treat the Restatement of Conflicts as authority for adherence to the rule of section 274(a). The judge hearing B’s petition is therefore bound to weigh in B’s favor that B’s reading of section 274(a) utilizes the analogy on which, according to the Restatement of Conflicts, section 274(a) is based, whereas the naïve reading (to which B’s is a reaction) ignores that analogy. But the judge is also bound to consider that on B’s reading, section 274(a) picks out the law of a state with which, as to accumulation of income, what is left of trust t1—viz., the fund that was once held by t1’s trustee(s) and is now the res of tn—has one of the least significant relationships among the states implicated in the CF-Set array.

The judge will consider, for example, that apart from the relation-back story about the terms of tn-1 being “read back into the instrument[s] creating” tn-2, tn-3, tn-4 . . . tn-x = t1, “the state where the [tn-1] trust instrument was executed and delivered” was presumably either State N-2 or State N-1, neither of which (we know) is State A. Likewise, “the state where the trust assets were . . . located” is unlikely to have been State A. Again, apart from the relation-back story about S’s being the donor of pn-2, pn-3, pn-4 . . . pn-x = p1 and, therefore, the settlor, for perpetuities purposes, of tn-2, tn-3, tn-4 . . . tn-x = t1, the settlor of tn-1, for state law purposes, was undoubtedly Dn-2, and “the state of the domicil of the settlor,” therefore, State N-2, which (we know) is not State A. We also know that “the state of the domicil of the beneficiaries” is not State A.

The result is that on B’s reading, section 274(a)’s choice of law is suboptimal from the point of view of the PF-Set. That is because on B’s reading, section 274(a) points to State A, and State A is not the state with which, as to accumulation of income, what is left of trust t1, viz., the fund that was once held by t1’s trustee(s) and is now the res of tn, has its most significant relationship. But a state’s rational policy is that the state’s own substantive law on trust validity should apply imperatively only when the state is the state to which the trust in question has its most significant relationship as to the matter at issue. Thus, on B’s reading, section 274(a) points uniquely to State A in circumstances in which, from State A’s point of view, State A is the wrong choice of law.

V. A Better Analogy to the Perpetuities Instantiation of the Relation Back Theory

Happily, our hypothetical judge (or the legislator to whom she describes her perplexity) can resist the conclusion that what causes the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) to go wrong on B’s reading is the analogy to the perpetuities instantiation (with its implicit commitment to the transitivity of the relation back theory). Happily because the judge (or her legislative counterpart) will be loath to depreciate section 274(a)’s signal credential qua jurisdiction-selecting, choice-of-law rule of being derivable or explicable by analogy to evidence in the local law of the forum for a general theoretical proposition of the common law. In fact, B’s own strategy of taking the analogy to the perpetuities instantiation of the relation back theory seriously can be used to impugn B’s reading of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) (Brute Transitivity Reading). For in its own way, that reading too is contrary to the relevant analogy.

A. Disanalogies

1. Chiasmus

One disanalogy concerns the perpetuities instantiation’s remotest date by which nonvested future interests created by a given exercise of a special power must vest, if at all, to be valid under the law of a state that has a RAP. In a case like our second case in point, the Brute Transitivity Reading analogizes the perpetuities instantiation’s must-vest-by date, not to the Settlor Autonomy Constraints, but to a particular, historical, attempted choice of law, viz., the designation made by the settlor of the first trust in the series t1, t2, t3 . . . tn-1. That seems an arbitrary feature in the choice-of-law instantiation given that as far as the perpetuities instantiation is concerned, the donee of a special (or testamentary general) power of appointment can postpone vesting to the very limit of the applicable perpetuities period—measured from the date of the creation rather than the exercise of the powerregardless of when future interests would vest according to the donor’s provision (if any) for takers in default. In the perpetuities instantiation, the donee of the power is limited by what the donor could have done in the way of postponing vesting not by what (if anything) the donor actually did in that vein.

In other words, the Brute Transitivity Reading crosses over the pairwise contrasts (1) between (a) the remotest date for vesting under an applicable RAP, on the one hand, and (b), for example, a particular specification of measuring lives, on the other, and (2) between (a) the Settlor Autonomy Constraints, on the one hand, and (b) a particular designation of state law to govern trust validity, on the other. A closer analogy between the choice-of-law and perpetuities instantiations of the relation back theory would take the Settlor Autonomy Constraints to be the choice-of-law counterpart of the perpetuities instantiation’s remotest date for vesting under an applicable RAP. That could make a difference whenever the Settlor Autonomy Constraints leave the settlor of a special-power-spawning trust two or more alternatives from which to choose in designating state law to govern the trust’s validity as to a particular matter at issue. That is a situation we have illustrated by supposing that in designating the law of State A to govern the validity of t1, S had merely acceded to the request of a commercial trustee organized under the laws of State A that she include in the t1 instrument certain “boilerplate” designating that state’s law to govern validity.

2. Missing “Blank”

Of course, to focus on the particular, historical designation of governing law made by the settlor of the first trust in a series like our t1, t2, t3 . . . tn-1 is to ignore all of the other designations made by the donees in the corresponding series D1, D2, D3 . . . Dn-2. That seems odd in light of what we have just observed: that what the donee of a special power actually does in the way of postponing vesting is carefully examined in the perpetuities instantiation. But it also seems odd given that apart from the preemptive force of section 274(a), the Restatement of Conflicts assumes that subject to constraints, the settlor of a trust can designate state law to govern trust validity. And, again, apart from the relation-back story that the settlor of the first trust in a series like our t1, t2, t3 . . . tn-1 is the settlor of each succeeding trust in the series, the settlors of the respective trusts t2, t3, t4 . . . tn-1, for state law purposes, were undoubtedly the donees D1, D2, D3 . . . Dn-2, respectively. If, for example, the donee D2 made provision in the terms of the t3 trust for takers in default of the exercise of p3 and (contrary to the facts of our second case in point) D3 simply failed to exercise p3, it would not be S’s but D2’s provision for takers in default that would control the disposition of the unappointed property subject to p3.

We have assumed that, in each case, the exercise of the special power held by the donees D1, D2, D3 . . . Dn-1 was within the scope of the power. That means that when S, settled t1, for example, she authorized D1 not only to “designate recipients of beneficial ownership interests” but also to create a further power of appointment, p2, and to name trustees (that is, to create t2). And if S did not expressly grant these additional powers, then because she did not expressly rule them out, the law inferred them. But if granting a power of appointment presumptively entails granting a power to create a trust, and the power to create a trust presumptively entails a power to designate the state law governing the validity of that trust, why should granting a power of appointment not presumptively entail granting a power to designate state law governing trust validity? Put another way: If the donor of a power of appointment is to be viewed as leaving blanks where she herself would otherwise have indicated the transferee(s) of property, whether the property would be transferred in trust, and, if so, what law would govern the validity of that trust, why should she be viewed as leaving blanks suitable only for naming transferees and indicating whether the transfer is to be in trust?

Thus, we can imagine for choice-of-law purposes, the settlor of a special-power-spawning trust t1 as leaving a further, metaphorical “blank” by filling in which the donee of the t1-spawned power can designate state law to govern trust validity (if she exercises the special power in further trust). Analogy to the perpetuities instantiation will recommend that the donee should be limited in her choice of law on trust validity to designations that the settlor of t1 could have made under the Settlor Autonomy Constraints if she (the settlor of t1), instead of leaving “blanks,” had decided to “fill in the blanks” herself so as to create t2 under the terms of t1. But with that limitation, allowing the donee of a trust-spawned special power that can properly be exercised in further trust to designate state law to govern the validity of a trust created by exercise of the power will yield a closer choice-of-law analogy to the perpetuities instantiation. It will also better reflect the general assumption that the power to create an express trust presumptively entails a power to designate state law to govern trust validity.

B. Enhancement Incidental to Reform

1. A Hypothetical Choice Situation

Reform of the disanalogy of the missing “blank,” then, yields that the donee of a trust-spawned special power that is properly exercised in further trust can designate state law governing trust validity. But in that case, the donee is limited to designations that the settlor-donor could have made if (contrary to fact) the settlor-donor had herself created the further trust under the terms of the power-spawning one. Thus, if a trust t1 that grants a special power p becomes irrevocable at time a, p is properly exercised at later time b to create a trust t2, and the t2 trust instrument designates the law of State N to govern the validity of t2, we want to know whether, consistent with the Settlor Autonomy Constraints of the Validity of Trust Rule, the settlor of t1 could have designated State N to govern the validity of t2 if instead of leaving “blanks” in the t1 trust instrument, she had decided to “fill in the blanks” herself as of time a, so as to bring about t2, under the terms of t1, as of time b.

2. Conditionalizing on a Future Substantial Relationship

Should we allow the settlor of t1 hypothetically to conditionalize on facts beyond her control that might increase or decrease the designation alternatives available to her (under the Settlor Autonomy Constraints) if the facts in question were certain, as of time a, to obtain by time b? Should we, for example, imagine the settlor’s providing in the hypothesized provision of the t1 trust instrument that designates state law to govern the validity of the future trust t2 that “if as of the time for the creation of t2 hereunder [that is, as of time b], the initial beneficiaries of t2 are domiciled in State N or the trust assets are then located in State N . . . ”? The analogy to the perpetuities instantiation suggests that we should. For though the period during which the exercise of a special power of appointment can postpone the vesting of a future interest is measured from the date on which the power is created, “[t]he words of the appointment [that is, the words in which the exercise is expressed] are to be interpreted in the light of circumstances existing at the time the power is exercised.”

A may bequeath his estate to B for life, remainder to such of B’s issue as B shall appoint by will. B has a son, C, who is born after A’s death, but who dies before B. Suppose B appoints “to the children of my son, C.” If we were to read this into the original instrument creating the power and construe it in the light of circumstances then existing, we would conclude that the appointment is bad. For C was, at that time, an unborn person; and a bequest to the children of an unborn person would be void [ab initio under the RAP]. But since C died before B, and B was in being when the power was created, it is certain that the interest created by the appointment will vest at B’s death. Hence the appointment is good.

If, on the facts of that illustration, it were certain as of the time of A’s death that C would later be born and predecease B, A could herself have made a bequest to C’s children without offending the RAP; for in that case, by hypothesis, the bequest would have been certain, as of the time of A’s death, to vest (if at all) within twenty-one years of the death of B, who was alive when A died. And that entails that A could have conditionalized on the facts in question in her will: a gift over (in default of B’s exercise of the testamentary special power) “to the children of any child (if any) of B who predeceases B” would have been good. Likewise, if, in our hypothetical choice situation, it were certain as of time a, that as of time b, the initial beneficiaries of t2 would be domiciled in State N, it would be available to the settlor of t1, as far as the policy of the substantial-relation requirement of the Settlor Autonomy Constraints is concerned, to designate State N regardless of whether that state has a “substantial relationship to [the] trust [t1 or the then-future trust t2] as of time a. For apart from the relation-back story about t2’s being created when the terms of the t1 trust instrument become irrevocable, the t2 trust (conjured in our hypothetical choice situation) is evidently created at time b.

Thus, reform of the disanalogy of the missing “blank” invites us to incorporate in our preferred interpretation of the choice-of-law analogy to the perpetuities instantiation yet another feature of the perpetuities instantiation, viz., willingness to interpret an appointment by the exercise of a special power in the light of circumstances existing at the time of the donee’s exercise insofar as those circumstances are outside of the donor’s control. For in the perpetuities instantiation, the donee of the special power in question is given the benefit of circumstances at the time of the donee’s exercise that are beyond the donor’s control and on which the donor could have conditionalized to create a valid nonvested interest as of the time she actually created the power instead. This is our cue to elaborate the hypothetical choice situation as follows. Supposing a trust t1 that grants a special power p becomes irrevocable at time a, that p is properly exercised at later time b to create a trust t2, and that the t2 trust instrument designates the law of State N to govern the validity of t2, the designation of State N will be respected if, consistent with the Settlor Autonomy Constraints, the settlor of t1 could have made the same designation for that purpose if (instead of leaving “blanks” in the t1 trust instrument) she had herself provided in the terms of t1 that t2 should be created as of b and had conditioned the designation of the law of State N to govern the validity of t2 on State N’s being implicated in the CF-Set as of time b.

3. Alternatively Conditionalizing on a Past Substantial Relationship

It happens that the sort of expository scheme of choice-of-law rules for which we are attempting to provide a functional validity-of-exercise rule for trust-spawned special powers of appointment—the sort of expository scheme exemplified by the Restatement of Conflictsignores conflicts in time. “The question occasionally arises whether a prior or subsequent law of a state should be applied, as, for example, when it is argued that a statute should be given a retroactive application.” “[Such questions] are not dealt with directly in the Restatement of [Conflicts].”

That means that in designing our hypothetical choice situation we can disregard the possibility that in the interval between times a and b, there will be a change in a strong public policy informing the local law of a state implicated in a CF-Set factor that is within the control of the settlor of t1 and which we may therefore want to be fixed for purposes of the hypothetical choice situation as of time a. In that case, the systemic irrelevance of conflicts in time means that it will be indifferent to us whether we (A) imagine the settlor of t1 (1) deliberating the designation of state law to govern the validity of t2 (because she is creating t2) at time a and (2) conditionalizing on connecting factors that are beyond her control as they will be at time b or, alternatively, (B) (1) conditionalize ourselves on connecting factors (and perhaps non-CF-Set facts liable to increase or decrease the designation alternatives available under the Settlor Autonomy Constraints) that are within the settlor of t1’s control as they were at time a and (2) imagine the settlor of t1 deliberating the designation (because she is just then herself creating t2) at time b.

To see this, let us suppose that on the same facts just described, we take the relevant CF-Set to comprise only (a) the place of business or domicile of the trustee, (b) the location of the trust assets, (c) the domicile of the beneficiaries, and the (d) domicile of the settlor. We are prepared, let us say, to regard items (a) through (c) as being beyond the settlor’s control for purposes of the settlor’s hypothetical conditionalizing but we do not think that the settlor’s changing her domicile (if she should) sometime after time a should have any effect on her hypothetical ability to designate the law of State N to govern the validity of t2.

In that case, the systemic irrelevance of potential conflicts in time means that we can ignore the possibility that a designation of state law to govern the validity of t2 that would have been permitted as of time a will, as of time b, violate a strong public policy of the state in which the settlor of t1 was domiciled as of time a. We can therefore ask either (A) whether the settlor of t1 could have, consistent with the Settlor Autonomy Constraints, designated the law of State N to govern the validity of t2 if she had herself provided, at time a, in the terms of t1, that t2 should be created as of time b and had conditioned the designation on State N’s being implicated in items (a) through (c) of the CF-Set as of time b or (B) whether the settlor of t1 could have, consistent with the Settlor Autonomy Constraints, designated the law of State N to govern the validity of t2 if she had herself created t2 at time b by a transfer of assets that she owned outright at that time, assuming that she was then domiciled in the state in which she was domiciled at time a and possessed the same (if any) non-CF-Set attributes affecting the choice of law that she possessed at time a.

As far as an expository scheme of choice-of-law rules like the Restatement of Conflicts is concerned, item (d) of the CF-Set refers to the same local law in both alternative hypothetical choice situation (A) and alternative hypothetical choice situation (B). For our purposes, then, even if there are factors in the CF-Set that we want to be fixed in the hypothetical choice situation as of time a, alternative hypothetical choice situations (A) and (B) are equivalent. And we can therefore prefer alternative (B) as the simpler of the two. If we do, our preferred formulation of the elaborated hypothetical choice situation is this. Supposing a trust t1 that grants a special power p becomes irrevocable at time a, that p is properly exercised at later time b to create a trust t2, and that the t2 trust instrument designates the law of State N to govern the validity of t2, the designation of State N for that purpose will be respected if the settlor of t1 could have, consistent with the Settlor Autonomy Constraints, made the same designation if she (1) had herself created t2 at time b by a transfer of assets that she then owned outright, (2) was domiciled at time b in the state in which she was domiciled at time a, and (3) possessed at time b the same (if any) non-CF-Set attributes affecting the choice of law that she possessed at time a.

VI. Validity of Exercise Tool Kit

The interpretation of the choice-of-law analogy to the perpetuities instantiation that alternative hypothetical choice situations (A) and (B) both express allows us to reformulate the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) in a way that shuns the Brute Transitivity Reading and that reading’s attendant embarrassment of policy. That interpretation also preserves and, indeed, strengthens the rule’s jurisprudentially favored claim to be derivable or explicable by analogy to evidence for the relation back theory in the local law of the forum. Deployment of the reformulated rule (Validity of Exercise Rule) requires some slight apparatus comprising an ordering rule and a few assumptions about the trust-validity, choice-of-law rules to which the Validity of Exercise Rule is accessory. The combination of the ordering rule, the relevant systemic assumptions, and the Validity of Exercise Rule may be formulated as follows.

A. The First Provision (and Herein of Systemic Assumptions)

The first provision is an ordering rule that gives the Validity of Exercise Rule priority over the Validity of Trust Rule. This may be a separate subsection of the Validity of Exercise Rule or an introductory phrase such as “Except as provided in Section X [the Validity of Exercise Rule] . . . ” prefixed to the Validity of Trust Rule. The effect is that both features of the Validity of Trust Rule, viz., its Settlor Autonomy Constraints and default designation, are made subject to the Validity of Exercise Rule so that the Validity of Trust Rule thus provides what it does provide except as otherwise provided in the Validity of Exercise Rule.

We can continue to prescind from the particulars of the Validity of Trust Rule’s formulation. We assume only that the Validity of Trust Rule includes (as just indicated) a set of constraints, like our Settlor Autonomy Constraints, limiting a settlor’s ability to designate state law to govern trust validity and a default designation; that it covers at least substantial validity; that the Settlor Autonomy Constraints involve a substantial-relation requirement and a public-policy override linked to something like the Restatement of Conflicts’ most-significant-relationship-as-to-the-matter-at-issue determination; that the substantiality of a state’s relation to a trust is determined in light of a CF-Set array that includes the domicile of the settlor at the time of the trust’s creation; and that the relative significance of a state’s relationship with a trust as to a given matter at issue is determined in light of a PF-Set that includes the protection of justified expectations or other aspects of formal justice.

B. The Validity of Exercise Rule Itself

The second provision of the validity of exercise tool kit is the Validity of Exercise Rule itself:

Section X: Validity of Exercise Rule

(a) Default: Except as provided in subsection (b), if an express trust t2 is purportedly created by the exercise of a special power of appointment p that is granted under the terms of a trust t1, the validity of t2 as to the matter at issue is determined by the local law that determines the validity of t1 as to that matter according to [the Trust Validity Rule] and, if applicable, this Section X [the Validity of Exercise Rule].

(b) Donee’s Ability to Designate State Law to Govern Trust Validity: If in the circumstances described in subsection (a), the power p is permitted, according to the local law that determines the validity of t1 as to permissible appointments under trust-spawned special powers, to be exercised in further trust, then unless the terms of t1 prohibit it, the donee of p may designate (with or without matter-specificity), subject to [the Settlor Autonomy Constraints of the Validity of Trust Rule], the state whose local law governs the validity of t2 as to the matter at issue provided the donee’s designation is one that the settlor of t1 could have made, consistent with that [set of Constraints], in light of the factors in the CF-Set as of the time p is exercised, if (contrary to fact) the settlor of t1 created t2 at that time by a transfer of property she then owned outright, assuming (regardless of fact) that she was then (i) domiciled in the state in which she was (in fact) domiciled when t1 became irrevocable and (ii) possessed of the same (if any) non-CF-Set attributes affecting the choice of law that she in fact possessed when t1 became irrevocable.

(c) Interpretations:

(1) For purposes of this Section X [the Validity of Exercise Rule]:

(A) Time of Exercise: A given exercise of a power of appointment occurs when that exercise becomes irrevocable without attribution.

(B) Time of Trust’s Creation: If an express trust t2 is created by the exercise of a special power of appointment p that is granted under the terms of a trust t1, t2 is created as of the time of that exercise of p without attribution.

(C) Identification of Settlor: If an express trust t2 is created by the exercise of a special power of appointment p that is granted under the terms of a trust t1, the settlor of t2 is the donee of p without attribution.

(D) Deemed Separate Trust within Previously Funded Trust: If a special power of appointment p that is otherwise described in subsection (b) is exercised not to create a new trust but to appoint assets of t1 to the trustee of a previously funded trust, the assets thus appointed are treated for purposes of subsection (b) as a separate trust t2 having the terms of the previously funded trust.

(E) Inferred Designation of Law to Govern Validity of Deemed Separate Trust: If in the circumstances described in subsection (c)(1)(D), the donee of the power p fails to make a separate designation (with or without matter-specificity) of a state whose local law governs the validity of the deemed separate trust t2 as to the matter at issue that satisfies the requirements of subsection (b), she is deemed to have attempted to designate for that purpose the state whose law governs the validity as to the matter at issue of the previously funded trust.

(2) Non-Attribution: For purposes of this subsection (c), “without attribution” means without regard to the common-law relation back theory of powers or any codification of that theory.

VII. Test Applications

How does the Validity of Exercise Rule perform in our special-power-elaborated first case in point and in our second case in point?

A. As to the Special-Power-Elaborated First Case in Point

Having abandoned our temporary assumption that Regulating State enacted UPAA section 103(2), we may assume that the Relaxed-State-dwelling donee of the t-spawned special power of appointment in our special-power-elaborated first case in point expressly designated the local law of Relaxed State to govern the validity of the t-mimic trust (with or without specific reference to the effect on S’s augmented estate for purposes of Regulating State’s forced share rule). In that case, the initial question under the Validity of Exercise Rule is whether in the Rule’s hypothetical choice situation, the settlor of trust t, viz., S, could designate the law of Relaxed State to govern the validity of the t-mimic trust as to its effect on S’s augmented estate. Could S make that designation, that is, consistent with the Validity of Trust Rule, in light of the factors in the CF-Set array as of the time the t-spawned power was exercised, if she had herself created the t-mimic trust at that time by a transfer of property she then owned outright, assuming she was then domiciled in Regulating State and was married?

There is no indication in the special-power-elaborated first case in point of any change in the CF-Set array during the interval between S’s creation of trust t and the exercise of the t-spawned special power. And we have assumed that given the CF-Set array at the creation of t, Regulating State’s interest in the determination of the effect of t on S’s augmented estate would outweigh that of Relaxed State under the Settlor Autonomy Constraints of the Validity of Trust Rule even if S should expressly designate (with or without matter-specificity) Relaxed State’s law to govern trust validity. Thus, S could not have designated the law of Relaxed State (in the Validity of Exercise Rule’s hypothetical choice situation) to govern the validity of t as to the effect on S’s augmented estate for purposes of Regulating State’s forced share rule.

That means (1) that the designation (with or without matter-specificity) by the donee of the t-spawned special power of the local law of Relaxed State to govern the validity of the t-mimic trust as to the effect on S’s augmented estate for purposes of Regulating State’s forced share rule will not be respected under the Validity of Exercise Rule and (2) that the validity of the t-mimic trust (as the intended result of the exercise of the t-spawned special power, as to the matter of its effect on S’s augmented estate) is determined by the law of Regulating State under the Validity of Trust Rule—either by its default designation or the policy override of the Settlor Autonomy Constraints. It also means that the Validity of Exercise Rule gets the same result in the special-power-elaborated first case in point that Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) does as written. That is not surprising; as we said, on the simple facts of our special-power-elaborated first case in point, the rule of section 274(a) foots the policy bill as formulated in the Restatement of Conflicts.

B. As to the Second Case in Point

It is on the facts of our second case in point that we expect the reformulation of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) as the Validity of Exercise Rule to do better than (as opposed to just as well as) the unreformed Restatement rule. For, unlike section 274(a) as formulated, the Validity of Exercise Rule resists the Brute Transitivity Reading. On the facts of our second case in point, the initial question according to the reformulation, is whether in the Validity of Exercise Rule’s hypothetical choice situation, Dn-2 could designate the law of State N to govern the validity of trust tn as to accumulation of income. Could Dn-2 make that designation, that is, consistent with the Validity of Trust Rule, in light of the factors in the CF-Set array as of the time the power pn-1 was exercised by Dn-1, if Dn-2 had herself created tn at that time by a transfer of property she then owned outright, assuming she was then domiciled in the state in which she was domiciled when tn-1 became irrevocable?

The answer will depend, of course, on the CF-Set. But, again, it may be doubted whether as of the time in question, State A is the state with which trust tn-1 has its most significant relationship as to any matter, and we have assumed that all of the other states implicated in the CF-Set have abrogated the rule against accumulations. So, Dn-2’s hypothetical designation of the law of State N to govern the validity of trust tn is unlikely to violate a strong public policy of the state (whichever it is) with which, as to accumulations, tn has its most significant relationship, and that means that under the Validity of Exercise Rule, the law of State N will be allowed to determine the validity of tn and its initial accumulation period.

C. What Has Become of the Transitivity of the Relation Back?

But if it should somehow fall out that Dn-2 could not have designated the law of State N to govern the validity of trust tn as to accumulations in the Validity of Exercise Rule’s hypothetical choice situation (because that designation in that situation would violate a strong public policy of the state with which, as to accumulation of income, tn has its most significant relationship), we would have to ask the same question about Dn-3 and the law of State N-1 given the CF-Set array as of the time pn-2 was exercised by Dn-2. This is because having recognized pn-1, tn-1, and tn in the description, in subsection (b) of the Validity of Exercise Rule, of p, t1, and t2,and having concluded (as we now suppose) that Dn-1’s designation of the law of State N to govern the validity of tn is not controlling, we would be thrown back, by the default in Validity of Exercise Rule subsection (a), on the state law that governs the validity of tn-1. Whereupon (because our second case in point involves a succession of successively generated trust-spawned special powers), we would recognize pn-2, tn-2, and tn-1 in subsection (b)’s description of (the power and trusts that it refers to as) “p,” “t1,” and “t2.” And off we would go again.

The recursive application of subsections (a) and (b) on facts like our second case in point is the Validity of Exercise Rule’s representation of the transitivity of the relation back in the perpetuities instantiation. If we had to ask the question, and it fell out that Dn-3 could not have designated the law of State N-1 to govern the validity of trust tn-1 as to accumulations in the Rule’s hypothetical choice situation (because that designation in that situation would violate a strong public policy of the state with which, as to accumulations, tn-1 has its most significant relationship), we would have to ask the same question about Dn-4 and the law of State N-2 given the CF-Set array as of the time pn-3 was exercised by Dn-3.

And we would go on in the same way until either (1) we found a state in the series State B, State C, State D . . . State N-1 designated by a donee in the series D1, D2, D3 . . . Dn-1 that that donee’s settlor-donor could have designated in the Validity of Exercise Rule’s hypothetical choice situation given the CF-Set array as of the time of the exercise of the relevant power in the series p1, p2, p3 . . . pn-1 or (2) we arrived (metaphorically) at a state picked out by the Validity of Trust Rule—either State N-x = State A (if S’s designation of State A in t1’s governing law provision does not violate a strong public policy of the state with which, as to accumulation of income, t1 has its most significant relationship) or, under the policy override of the Settlor Autonomy Constraints, the state (whichever it is) with which, as to accumulation of income, t1 has its most significant relationship.

D. A Third Case in Point

We can illustrate the latter state of affairs by assuming that the beneficiaries of the trust t1 described in our second case in point are a proper subset (Disparaged Gentes) of the descendants of S’s great-grandparents that S wanted to use part of her vast wealth to make beholden to another proper subset of those descendants (Exalted Gens) for as long as any member of the Exalted Gens should be willing and able to serve as a trustee. T1 was therefore constituted as a “perpetual trust.” The trustees were given discretionary distribution powers. Trustee succession and the class of permissible objects of the power p1 were both strictly based on heredity. And effective exercise of p1 was expressly conditioned on (1) the appointment’s being in trust for so long as any member of the Exalted Gens should be willing and able to serve as a trustee, (2) perpetuation under the appointive trust of t1’s limitations on trustee liability, and (3) explicit imposition, in the instrument of exercise, of all the t1 trust instrument’s limitations on p1 (including this “transitivity constraint”) on any power of appointment granted by the exercise of p1.

S’s domicile as of the time t1 became irrevocable was State A, which, then as now, permits express trusts having definite or definitely ascertainable beneficiaries to be “perpetual.” But S chose to site t1’s administration in State W[ild ]W[est] and to designate State WW in t1’s governing law provision (concerning validity as well as construction and administration) because, then as now, State WW is the only state under whose local law t1’s “Absolute Exculpation of Trustee(s)” provision is enforceable. That provision was due partly to S’s ambition for perpetuity: she reasonably thought that the greatest possible immunity from liability for breach of trust would remove an important disincentive for members of the Exalted Gens to serve as trustee.

But the “Absolute Exculpation of Trustee(s)” provision was also connected with S’s conception of t1 primarily as a sustained, transactional assertion of the superiority of the Exalted Gens’ breeding over that of the Disparaged Gentes. To S’s mind at least, that assertion had nothing to do with the notion of service normally associated with trusteeship. There is, indeed, a sense in which the Disparaged Gentes are merely incidental beneficiaries of t1. But as S realized, that sense threatened S’s enterprise. For whereas S intended that the trust (or its ramifications through exercises of trust-spawned special powers) should last for as long as the Exalted Gens continues, none of the states with which S was willing that t1 should have a “substantial relation,” including State WW, will suffer a noncharitable purpose trust to last for more than two or three decades. Hence the t1 trust instrument contains, in addition to the “Absolute Exculpation of Trustee(s)” provision, a declaration that economic benefit to deserving members of the Disparaged Gentes is one of the trust’s “material purposes.”

In this third case in point, State WW is designated in the governing law provision of each of the trusts t1, t2, t3 . . . tn. And the beneficiary B has petitioned a court in State N-1 (the state of Dn-1’s and, let us say, B’s domicile) for an order surcharging—for the benefit of all potential distributees of tn’s income or principal—the trustee of tn, T, for damages attributable to a breach of trust that was (B alleges) clearly committed with reckless indifference to the interest of the beneficiaries. T, of course, will point to the tn trust instrument’s reiteration of t1’s “Absolute Exculpation of Trustee(s)” provision and to Dn-1’s designation of the law of State WW to govern trust validity.

B will point to the Validity of Exercise Rule, under which the initial question is whether in the Validity of Exercise Rule’s hypothetical choice situation, Dn-2 could have designated the law of State WW to govern the validity of trust tn as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation. Could Dn-2 make that designation, that is, consistent with the Validity of Trust Rule, in light of the factors in the CF-Set array as of the time the power pn-1 was exercised by Dn-1, if she had herself created tn at that time by a transfer of property she then owned outright, assuming she was then domiciled in the state in which she was domiciled when tn-1 became irrevocable?

The answer will depend on the CF-Set. But if the judge hearing B’s petition finds that the state with which trust tn has its most significant relationship as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation is any state other than State WW, she will be bound to find that that Dn-2 could not have designated the law of State WW to govern the validity of trust tn as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation in the Validity of Exercise Rule’s hypothetical choice situation because that designation in that situation would violate a strong public policy of the state (whichever it is) with which, as to fiduciary exculpation, tn has its most significant relationship. That is so because we know that State WW is the only state under whose law tn’s “Absolute Exculpation of Trustee(s)” provision is enforceable, and that outside of State WW, the trustee’s duty to perform the trust honestly and in good faith for the benefit of the beneficiaries is said to constitute the “irreducible core” of an express trust having definite or definitely ascertainable beneficiaries.

In that case, having recognized pn-1, tn-1, and tn in Validity of Exercise Rule subsection (b)’s description of “p,” “t1,” and “t2,” and concluded that Dn-1’s designation of the law of State WW to govern the validity of tn is not controlling, the judge would be thrown back, by the default rule of subsection (a) of the Validity of Exercise Rule, on the state law that governs the validity of tn-1 as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation. Whereupon (because our third case in point involves a succession of successively generated trust-spawned special powers), the judge would recognize pn-2, tn-2, and tn-1 in subsection (b)’s description of “p,” “t1,” and “t2.” She would then turn to the question whether Dn-3 could have designated the law of State WW to govern the validity of trust tn-1 as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation in the Rule’s hypothetical choice situation given the CF-Set array as of the time pn-2 was exercised by Dn-2.

And for exactly the same reasons she concluded that Dn-1’s designation of the law of State WW to govern the validity of tn is not controlling as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation, the judge would conclude that Dn-2’s designation of the law of State WW to govern the validity of tn-1 is not controlling as to that matter. For, again, State WW is the only state under whose law tn-1’s “Absolute Exculpation of Trustee(s)” provision is enforceable, and outside of State WW, the trustee’s duty to perform the trust honestly and in good faith for the benefit of the beneficiaries is said to constitute the “irreducible core” of an express trust having definite or definitely ascertainable beneficiaries.

At this point, the judge can see that on the facts of our third case in point, each recursive application of the Validity of Exercise Rule is going to yield the same conclusion, for the same reasons, until we recognize in Validity of Exercise Rule subsection (b)’s description of “p,” “t1,” and “t2,” pn-x = p1, tn-x = t1, and tn-y = t2. The question then will be whether S could have designated the law of State WW to govern the validity of trust t2 as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation in the Rule’s hypothetical choice situation given the CF-Set array as of the time the power p1 was exercised by D1. The answer will be No, and we will be thrown back, again, by the default rule of subsection (a) of the Validity of Exercise Rule, on the state law that governs the validity of t1 as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation. But here the recursive application of the Validity or Exercise Rule halts; for unlike the trusts t2, t3, t4 . . . tn, trust t1 was not created by the exercise of a special power of appointment.

The ultimate application of the Validity of Exercise Rule on the facts of our third case in point, then, is a postmortem application of the Validity of Trust Rule, pursuant to Validity of Exercise Rule subsection (a), to t1 to determine the state law that governs the validity, as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation, of what is left of that trust, viz., the fund that was once held by t1’s trustee(s) and is now the res of tn. The initial question in that application is whether S’s designation of the law of State WW to govern the validity of t1 violates a strong public policy of the state with which, as to fiduciary exculpation, what is left of t1 has its most significant relationship. On our heuristic assumption that the judge hearing B’s petition has found that the state with which trust tn has its most significant relationship as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation is some state other than State WW, the answer will be Yes (it does violate such a policy). For, once again, State WW is the only state under whose law S’s “Absolute Exculpation of Trustee(s)” provision is enforceable, and outside of State WW, the trustee’s duty to perform the trust honestly and in good faith for the benefit of the beneficiaries is said to constitute the “irreducible core” of an express trust having definite or definitely ascertainable beneficiaries.

VIII. Conclusion

The upshot is that in our third case in point, the state law that governs the validity of trust tn as to fiduciary exculpation is, by virtue of subsection (a) of the Validity of Exercise Rule, the Validity of Trust Rule’s default designation of the (non-State-WW) state (whichever it is) with which t1 has its most significant relationship as to the scope of fiduciary exculpation. That determination is made in default of S’s impermissible designation of State WW in t1’s governing law provision, which means that on the facts of our third case in point, the Validity of Exercise Rule goes “back” (within the meaning of the relation back theory) as far as Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) does on the Brute Transitivity Reading.

The difference is that whereas Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) always goes back, on the Brute Transitivity Reading, to the first trust in a series like our t1, t2, t3 . . . tn-1, the Validity of Exercise Rule does so only if none of the associated donee-settlors D1, D2, D3 . . . Dn-1 makes a choice-of-law designation that satisfies Validity of Exercise Rule subsection (b): it has to be a case (like our third case in point) in which not one of those donee-settlors manages to make a designation that her immediate predecessor in the series could have made (consistent with the Settlor Autonomy Constraints) in the Rule’s hypothetical choice situation. In that extremity, the state law that governs the validity of trust tn as to the matter at issue is ultimately determined by direct application of the Trust Validity Rule under the auspice of Validity of Exercise Rule subsection (a). But otherwise, the Validity of Exercise Rule is distinguished from the Brute Transitivity Reading of section 274(a) by its insistence, in its subsection (b), on the realization of the assumption—of the Restatement of Conflicts as reflected in the Validity of Trust Rule—that a power to appoint trust assets in further trust presumptively entails a power to designate state law to govern trust validity.

The Brute Transitivity Reading invariably betrays that assumption in situations involving a succession of successively generated, trust-spawned special powers, by ignoring any express designation of state law to govern trust validity that is made by the real settlors of all but the first trust in a series like our t1, t2, t3 . . . tn-1. And that betrayal depreciates the analogy to the local law (viz., the perpetuities instantiation of the relation back theory) on which the rule of Restatement of Conflicts section 274(a) is expressly based. By rehabilitating the analogy in that respect, the Validity of Exercise interpretation of section 274(a) not only avoids the embarrassment of policy to which the Brute Transitivity Reading exposes the rule of that section but also enhances the rule’s credential as a jurisdiction-selecting, choice-of-law rule that can be derived or explained by analogy to evidence in the local law of the forum for a general theoretical proposition of the common law.

The Validity of Exercise Rule is, therefore, the preferred interpretation of the choice-of-law rule on the substantial validity of exercises of trust-spawned special powers that is described in section 274(a) of the Restatement of Conflicts. That rule is required to prevent settlors from circumventing the Validity of Trust Rule’s Settlor Autonomy Constraints (and thus eluding local-law restrictions on express trusts) simply by interposing a special power of appointment. Being required for that purpose, the Validity of Exercise Rule is a necessary adjunct to the validity-of-trust, choice-of-law rules of any state that wants to regulate what domestic settlors can do with express trusts in any particular respect in which another state is, or may be, more relaxed. And unless it is constitutionally laissez-faire, every state has to regulate what settlors can do with express trusts in some respect in which another state is, or may be, more relaxed.

    Author