Qualified immunity, the defense afforded to police officers and other government actors to civil rights claims under 42 U.S.C. § 1983, continues to be a hot-button issue when discussing police reform. The defense shields officers (and other government actors) even when they violate someone’s civil rights so long as the officer’s conduct does not violate “clearly established” law. To overcome a qualified immunity defense, the U.S. Supreme Court has required the “clearly established” law to be defined at a high level of specificity. In other words, an officer is unlikely to face liability unless past cases with very similar factual scenarios have already held that the officer’s conduct is violative of someone’s rights. This “clearly established” law test has faced significant scrutiny, most notably from the anchor of the Court’s current conservative wing, Justice Clarence Thomas.
Justice Thomas has called the Court’s current “clearly established” law standard into question on multiple occasions (see, e.g., Hoggard v. Rhodes, 141 S. Ct. 2421 (2021) (Thomas, J., statement respecting the denial of certiorari); Ziglar v. Abbasi, 137 S. Ct. 1843 (2017) (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment); Baxter v. Bracey, 140 S. Ct. 1862 (2020) (Thomas, J., dissenting from the denial of certiorari)). According to Justice Thomas, the Court’s “clearly established” law standard for qualified immunity is not rooted in the text or common law backdrop against which Congress enacted 42 U.S.C. § 1983 (Hoggard, 141 S. Ct. at 2421–22 (Thomas, J., statement respecting the denial of certiorari)). Rather, it is rooted in the Court’s attempt to balance competing values (see Ziglar, 137 S. Ct. at 1872 (noting that the Court has “acknowledged, in fact, that the ‘clearly established’ standard is designed to ‘protect the balance between vindication of constitutional rights and government officials’ effective performance of their duties’” (citation omitted)); Baxter, 140 S. Ct. at 1864 (noting that “the Court adopted the test . . . because of a ‘balancing of competing values’”)). As Justice Thomas notes, “The Constitution assigns this kind of balancing to Congress, not the Courts” (Ziglar, 137 S. Ct. at 1872). Thus, in coming up with the “clearly established” law standard for qualified immunity, Justice Thomas argues that the Court was not “engaged in ‘interpreting the intent of Congress in enacting’ the Act [giving rise to civil rights claims under § 1983]” (id. at 1871 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment) (citation omitted)). Rather, the Court’s “qualified immunity precedents instead represent precisely the sort of ‘freewheeling policy choices’ that we have previously disclaimed the power to make” (id.). In other words, in crafting the “clearly established” law test, the Court “substitute[d] [its] own policy preferences for the mandates of Congress” (id. at 1872).
Given that the Court’s “clearly established” law test for qualified immunity has stood for more than 40 years, one might think the Court is unlikely to hear Justice Thomas’s calls to reexamine the doctrine. However, the Court’s recent approach to stare decisis, as highlighted in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization, 142 S. Ct. 2228 (2022), seems to suggest that this Court is open (and some might say eager) to reexamine and potentially overrule a plethora of cases, including the “clearly established” law standard for qualified immunity.
A Five-Justice Majority Appears Ready to Shake Things Up
Before considering the possibility of the Court’s reexamining its qualified immunity jurisprudence, it is important to understand the Court’s current thinking on precedent and stare decisis as embodied by the majority’s decision in Dobbs. In Dobbs, a five-justice majority consisting of Justice Samuel Alito, Justice Thomas, Justice Neil Gorsuch, Justice Brett Kavanaugh, and Justice Amy Coney Barrett overturned a half century of settled law giving women the right to an abortion. A discussion of the abortion right discarded in Dobbs is far beyond the scope of this article. However, Dobbs is remarkable not just because of the Court’s dramatic shift on abortion but also because it represents a potentially dramatic shift on stare decisis.
The maxim from Justice Louis Brandeis had long held: “Stare decisis is usually the wise policy, because in most matters it is more important that the applicable rule of law be settled than that it be settled right” (Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., 52 S. Ct. 443, 447 (1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting)). But in Dobbs, the majority noted “that stare decisis is ‘not an inexorable command’” before making clear that at least in matters of interpretation of the Constitution, it viewed having the issue “settled right” in their eyes to be of paramount importance (see Dobbs, 142 S. Ct. at 2262 (noting that “when it comes to the interpretation of the Constitution . . . we place a high value on having the matter ‘settled right’”; the majority then went on to upset a well-settled constitutional precedent over three dissents and one concurrence in the judgment (Chief Justice John Roberts did not concur with the portion of the decision that completely discards the right to an abortion recognized in Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973)))).
While the Dobbs majority claimed that its approach to stare decisis is nothing out of the ordinary, it very possibly marked a dramatic shift and highlighted that this five-justice majority does not feel restricted from overturning long-settled precedent if it believes that precedent is “egregiously wrong.” The Dobbs majority claimed that its decision to overrule Roe and Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992), was warranted by an application of “traditional stare decisis factors” and that it had not “abandoned” stare decisis (Dobbs, 142 S. Ct. at 2278–79). Needless to say, the three-judge dissent did not see it that way. To the dissent, the majority ignored “traditional principles of stare decisis” (id. at 2347 (Breyer, J., dissenting)) and instead “substitute[d] a rule by judges for the rule of law” (id. at 2335). According to the dissent, under the majority’s “cavalier approach to overturning [the] Court’s precedents,” “[t]he Court departs from its obligation to faithfully and impartially apply the law” (id. at 2320). Under this new approach, “proclivities of individuals rule” (id.), and any precedent is at risk of being overturned so long as “a bare majority of the present Court disagrees” with it (id. at 2335). It is worth noting that these five justices’ approach also appears to be out of step with Chief Justice Roberts’s preference for a “more measured course” (id. at 2310 (Roberts, C.J., concurring in the judgment); see also id. at 2349–50 (Breyer, J., dissenting) (noting that while the dissent disagreed with Chief Justice Roberts’s approach, “no one should think that there is not a large difference” between Chief Justice Roberts’s approach and that of the five-justice majority); id. at 2281 (the majority noting “serious problems” with Chief Justice Roberts’s “more measured course”)).
Legal commentators will no doubt wrestle with whether the majority, the dissent, or the chief justice has the better argument regarding the proper approach to stare decisis, and this article does not weigh into that discussion. Quite simply, the purpose of the above discussion is to highlight that this current five-justice majority appears more open to revisiting and overturning settled law.