IV. Twenty-First Century Doctrinal Developments that Warrant Doctrinal or Legislative Change
In this part we identify concerns that Delaware law may have again created unnecessary complexity and potential for systemic unfairness and propose solutions to make Delaware law more functional and predictable.
A. The Continued and Expanded Life of Lynch’s Inherent Coercion Theory and Its Negative Consequences
As described earlier, MFW reined in Lynch’s “inherent coercion” rationale and the mischief it caused in connection with going private mergers. The Delaware Supreme Court’s affirming decision in that case, and its later decision in Flood v. Synutra International, Inc., essentially rejected the inherent coercion theory and restored traditional principles for determining the standard of judicial review applicable to conflict transactions. It did so by recognizing that (i) independent directors and stockholders can exercise real leverage and make informed choices when faced with a conflict transaction involving a controller, and (ii) Delaware law is vibrant enough to protect minority stockholders from retribution by a controller that did not get its way.
At the same time, MFW and its progenitors viewed going private mergers as a context in which the dangers of overreaching are particularly grave, and therefore developed a bespoke solution that could invoke the business judgment rule. We did not view those decisions as imposing that solution on all controlling stockholder conflict transactions, but as instead normalizing the approach Delaware law would take to controller transactions and to treat them equally with other conflict transactions, at the very least where what was at issue was not a transaction or decision that required both the approval of the board and the approval of stockholders under the Delaware General Corporation Law (“DGCL”).
But the common law evolves on a case-by-case basis, and precedent is sometimes applied, in good faith, in a manner that the decisions did not intend or contemplate. That is what seems to have happened in the wake of MFW, leading to a phenomenon we describe occasionally as “MFW creep.” Rather than confining MFW to the going private merger context for which that case was specifically designed, plaintiffs have successfully urged Chancery in several cases to require the full MFW suite of protections for any conflict transaction with a controlling stockholder, in order to invoke business judgment review, even where no statutory vote is required. The decisions that take this view are grounded not in reasoning in the cases leading up to MFW, but in Lynch’s inherent coercion logic, which those cases cast doubt upon, and which MFW and Flood implicitly abandoned. Admittedly, the decisions culminating in MFW necessarily referred to the inherent coercion doctrine in a way that was respectful, but in our view, clearly indicating that the doctrine was not convincing. But, instead of reading MFW as a move away from the inherent coercion doctrine toward the traditional approach, the recent Chancery cases have instead taken the view that inherent coercion exists in any situation where a controller has a conflict.
By way of leading example, in a scholarly and encyclopedic decision, the Court of Chancery in EZCORP reviewed the post-Lynch case law and concluded that the weight of authority did not cabin Lynch to the going private context, but applied its inherent coercion doctrine to all conflict transactions involving controllers. In so doing, the court cited decisions leading up to MFW that said otherwise, including Friedman v. Dolan, Canal Capital Corp. v. French, and Tyson, an important Chancery decision holding that because a special committee of independent directors approved executive compensation to a member of a controlling stockholder’s family, the business judgment standard applied.
EZCORP concluded, however, that cases like Tyson, which applied traditional Delaware corporate law to controller transactions not requiring a statutory vote, were not persuasive, because it viewed the inherent coercion theory of Lynch as a continuing principle of the corporate common law. In adopting that view, EZCORP relied upon the power of a controlling stockholder to wield influence at both the board level and the stockholder level, to justify subjecting any controller conflict transaction to the entire fairness standard, even a transaction not requiring a stockholder vote. Nevertheless, EZCORP was careful to indicate that the Delaware Supreme Court had not spoken to the question of whether the MFW dual process approach was required outside of the going private merger context, or whether use of any of the traditional cleansing devices would henceforth suffice, to invoke business judgment review.
We would answer that question differently than EZCORP and would not apply MFW to all transactions with controlling stockholders: the MFW solution was tailored specifically to the problem created by the Lynch line of cases, namely that those cases created poor incentives in the going private merger context for transactional planners and encouraged wasteful litigation yielding no benefit for investors or society. The solution MFW embraced credits procedures that, if implemented with fidelity, give minority stockholders in a squeeze-out merger the key protections they would receive in a merger with a third-party acquiror: (i) fiduciaries actively negotiating for their benefit and (ii) the right to determine for themselves as stockholders whether the transaction is in their best interests. This solution addressed concerns unique to the controller going private context: the requirement that the controller concede that the special committee of independent directors could say no responded directly to the concern that the controller could bypass that committee decision by presenting a tender offer directly to the minority stockholders.
The MFW solution was never designed to apply to all transactions between controlling stockholders and companies. MFW repeatedly emphasized that it was addressing only the context of going private mergers: it defined the question presented as “what should be the correct standard of review for mergers between a controlling stockholder and its subsidiary,” and recited that “[o]utside the controlling stockholder merger context, it has long been the law that even when a transaction is an interested one but not requiring a stockholder vote, Delaware law has invoked the protections of the business judgment rule when the transaction was approved by disinterested directors acting with due care.” Thus, the idea that MFW meant, without saying so, to define the treatment of all transactions with controlling stockholders is at odds with MFW’s own text.
It is also at odds with widespread practice. One of the historical functions of audit committees has been to review and approve such related party transactions, and controlling stockholders—many of which are businesses themselves—often provide or acquire services or goods to or from the controlled company. Likewise, controlling stockholder representatives often serve and are compensated as executives, and compensation committees comprised of independent directors were developed in part to address the potential for such conflicts. We never understood that entire fairness review would be universally required in these common situations, or that the potential for controller self-dealing makes it impossible for the company’s directors to avoid a judicial fairness inquiry.
Rather, if one of the traditional cleansing techniques is used, the presumption should be that the transaction or compensation was approved by impartial fiduciaries who could faithfully represent the company’s interest in getting a fair deal for itself. In that case, the business judgment rule would apply unless the plaintiff could use the waste doctrine to create an inference that an “apparently well motivated board” might not have been. The plaintiff could use this equitable “safety hatch” by pleading that the “decision is so far beyond the bounds of reasonable judgment that it seems essentially inexplicable on any ground other than bad faith.”
Section 144 of the DGCL further supports this view. The techniques that statute requires to validate an interested transaction largely reflect those that the common law of corporations had deemed necessary for the transaction to receive the protection of the business judgment rule, rather than inflexibly remain subject to entire fairness review. With important judicial adaptations to maintain credibility—e.g., the cleansing vote must be one of only the disinterested stockholders, and special committee members must be independent as well as disinterested—the techniques prescribed in § 144 were considered sufficiently robust to eliminate the need for a fairness inquiry. Just as § 144 was built on equity cases involving fiduciary duty, and not just technical legal validity, later equity cases were built on the foundation established by § 144’s codification of the then-recognized techniques for addressing conflict transactions.
In stating that, we do not exaggerate the consistency or precision with which Delaware case law addressed the standard of review ultimately applicable to conflict transactions. In earlier eras, the costs of discovery and the volume of cases facing corporations were smaller, and the importance of determining whether a case should proceed past the pleading stage was not as salient.
We also acknowledge the many cases stating that any conflicted self-dealing transaction with a controlling stockholder is subject initially to the entire fairness standard. Vice Chancellor Laster’s exhaustive review of cases in his scholarly EZCORP decision well documents that reality. And as far as that goes, we agree with that proposition. But that proposition does not, in itself, answer the important question the Delaware Supreme Court has yet to answer post-MFW: outside of the going private context, what cleansing techniques will change that initial standard from entire fairness to business judgment review?
When Function Over Form was published, independent directors had already shown themselves capable of standing up to corporate managers, and CEO tenure had been declining as a result. Independent directors increasingly owed their continued access to directorships not to ties to management, but to their willingness to support policies that powerful institutional investors liked. These same institutional investors had shown themselves willing to criticize companies—including those with controlling stockholders—and to dissent at the ballot box. Moreover, Delaware courts had proven vigilant in policing electoral manipulation and coercion of stockholders in the voting process, and would readily address any controller who reacted to a negative vote with retribution. Likewise, even controllers had to be sensitive to the prospect that replacing independent directors who said no to a conflict transaction with ones who would do their bidding would impair their ability to raise debt and other capital. Decisions of the Delaware courts and actions by the U.S. Securities and Exchange Commission had enhanced the information base available to stockholders about salient developments like M&A transactions. For those reasons, Function Over Form argued that Lynch’s inherent coercion theory was empirically baseless.
Market activity since then has only strengthened that argument. Institutional investors have a powerful voice and no fear of controlling stockholders or corporate management. Stockholders challenge them frequently, and they have hedge funds and the media to help them. Independent directors are under great scrutiny too, and they are expected to act aggressively in M&A situations to make sure that the public investors get a good deal. Proxy advisors and analysts scrutinize deals and help institutional investors decide how to vote. Annual say-on-pay votes exist at most companies, and independent directors who run afoul of investor and proxy advisor sentiment over pay policies at one company (even ones with a controlling stockholder) can face withhold votes at other companies on whose boards they serve. In light of these market developments, all of the constraints discussed earlier—judicial review under the entire fairness standard where a controller replaces directors who stand in its way, the prospect of adverse effects on financing, and reputational damage with institutional investors and the press—would at least as forcefully deter a controller in settings involving conflict transactions other than going private mergers. Thus, even more now than when Function Over Form was published, there is no reason to base the law on the view that stockholders cannot protect themselves at the ballot box, or that independent directors do not take their duties seriously when considering conflict transactions.
The retributive rationale underlying the inherent coercion doctrine has also been undercut in a decisive way by MFW, if it and its predecessors are taken seriously. As we have discussed, Lynch’s inherent coercion doctrine rested on the premise that a controller could bypass a special committee, make a going private tender offer, and escape ultimate fairness review. That premise, unique to the going private context, would disappear if the Delaware Supreme Court were to make clear that a going private tender offer by a controller would be subject to the same level of judicial review as a going private merger, and the condition in MFW that the controller cannot bypass the special committee or the minority stockholders would be rendered superfluous. Put simply, if, as MFW, Cox, Pure, and leading scholars suggest, the equitable review of a going private transaction should not be driven primarily by statutory form, especially when the merger route is more protective of minority stockholders, a foundational premise of the entire Lynch doctrine goes away.
For these reasons, MFW should be viewed as articulating a targeted solution to a targeted problem created in large measure by the anomaly in the case law arguably allowing a controller to use a tender offer to escape both a special committee’s veto and fairness review, and not as prescribing a rigid set of procedures applicable to any transaction between a controlling stockholder and a company. Given the importance of going private mergers and the concerns this anomaly creates, we embrace the principled approach MFW took to replicating the protections afforded to stockholders under the DGCL in a third-party, arm’s-length merger. Because this bypass anomaly does not exist in other settings and because the inherent coercion doctrine is flawed and should not form a further basis for making corporate common law, we would not extend MFW beyond the going private context. But if it is to be extended, at most MFW’s two key protections should apply when a self-dealing transaction is statutorily required to be approved by stockholders. Applying MFW when a self-dealing transaction must be approved by the stockholders and the board would have some logic, because it would match the basic reasoning of the decision. But where no stockholder vote is required, MFW’s procedures have no fit, and their extension to such contexts involves judicial action better described as statute writing.
Extending Lynch’s inherent coercion doctrine after MFW had effectively rejected it, thereby dooming to failure any motion to dismiss unless the controller employs the costly MFW procedures, will not generate systemic value for diversified stockholders. Instead, it is more likely to result in excessive transaction costs, increased D&O insurance costs, and contrived settlements designed only to avoid the costs of discovery and justify the attorneys’ fee that motivates most corporate representative suits.
Corporate law is not designed for perfection. Although fairness is important, and investors must have protections against abuse, investors and society risk much if courts act as if they can capably address all situational concerns, and impose a toll on innovation, flexibility, and the cost of capital by facilitating litigation rent-seeking in situations when sufficient, intra-corporate guarantees of fairness have been employed. Corporate jurisprudence cannot require a microscopic review of every situation that might involve unfairness. Rather, it must rely on rules that incentivize the use of high-integrity procedures in most cases and reduce the costs to society and investors of litigation and judicial second-guessing.
Accordingly, Delaware law should embrace the direction of MFW and Function Over Form, by reaffirming that most conflict transactions, even with a controlling stockholder, receive the protection of the business judgment rule if one of the three traditional cleansing procedures is credibly employed. Given vibrant stockholder power, the increased information available to them and the plaintiffs who represent them, the reputational and electoral implications for independent directors who bend to controllers’ wills, and the potent ability of Chancery to police retribution by a controller that does not get its way, the benefits of the traditional approach outweigh the risks, and plaintiffs’ lawyers would be encouraged to win cases on the merits, not extract fees based on an overly litigation-intensive standard of review.
B. Expanding MFW by Expanding the Definition of “Controlling Stockholder”
The “MFW creep” described in the previous section has been exacerbated by expanding the definition of a “controlling stockholder.” If pleading that a conflict transaction involves a “controlling stockholder” inexorably requires a trial on entire fairness, the occasion for such after-the-fact economic review expands if courts expand the definition of a controlling stockholder.
Under Delaware law, it was historically difficult to establish that a stockholder having less than majority ownership was a controlling stockholder. Even in Aronson, where the main defendant, the former CEO and chairman, controlled 47 percent of the vote, had close affiliations with several directors, and had an ongoing consulting arrangement, the court declined to infer control at the pleading stage.
Kahn v. Lynch took a more expansive view of the term “controlling stockholder.” Alcatel, a 43.3 percent stockholder that was contractually limited to electing a minority of the board, was nonetheless found to be a controlling stockholder, based on evidence that the non-management directors had previously accepted Alcatel’s refusal to renew management contracts that those directors had supported. Following Lynch, the Court of Chancery in Cysive determined that the founder, CEO, and chairman of the company, who owned 35 percent of the shares (but effectively 40 percent, taking into account stock options and shares owned by family members and subordinates), was a controlling stockholder. The court reasoned that he owned a large enough percentage of shares to be a dominant force in any contested election and exercise managerial supremacy over the company. Still, the court’s reasoning remained deeply tied to voting, not just managerial power: as the court explained, “the analysis of whether a controlling stockholder exists must take into account whether the stockholder, as a practical matter, possesses a combination of stock voting power and managerial authority that enables him to control the corporation, if he so wishes.” And some subsequent rulings have been cautious in determining that a minority holder with a significant role in the company was a controller.
Our concern, however, is that the revival of Lynch’s inherent coercion theory has created pressure to expand the definition of controlling stockholder to reach persons having far less than a voting majority but are either critically important to the company or associated with other stockholders as a group. Tesla Motors illustrates the first of these two categories. Tesla’s CEO, Elon Musk, held only about 22 percent of the company’s voting power, but, taking into account apparent board level conflicts and Musk’s acknowledgements that he had substantial influence over the company and the board, the court found a reasonable inference that Musk was a controlling stockholder.
Although that finding may have been appropriate, we are concerned that the court’s reasoning in applying controlling stockholder doctrine sweeps too broadly. Even if Musk were not a controller, the finding that a majority of the directors were beholden to Musk would in itself invoke fairness review and demand excusal under the first prong of Aronson. The other finding—that Musk was so talented and visionary that the company could not succeed without him—does not rationally imply that someone is a controlling stockholder. Being valuable to the company does not make an executive a controlling stockholder, nor does it implicate the concerns underlying Lynch—namely, the potential to use affirmative voting power to unseat directors and implement transactions that the minority stockholders do not like, and use blocking voting power to impede other transactions.
The second avenue for expanding the controlling stockholder definition is to aggregate the voting power of stockholders holding blocs of shares, even though they are not bound by a voting agreement or founding family ties. These stockholders are then treated as a “control group” with the same force and effect on the standard of review as if they were a majority stockholder. If the only rationale for this treatment of otherwise disaggregated stockholders is that they had a similar view about a specific transaction’s favorability, despite having no obligation or prior record of being tied together as to all issues, this mode of “situational control group” analysis should be applied with great caution. Aggregating into a single unit stockholders united only by a common view of what will optimize the value of their shares would enable plaintiffs to survive a motion to dismiss with no further proof that these stockholders, even if they hold fiduciary positions, breached their duty of loyalty.
To cabin this danger, the Delaware Supreme Court has required plaintiffs seeking to establish that the defendants are part of a control group to demonstrate that they entered into a contract, common ownership, agreement, or other arrangement where they worked toward a common goal. Although several opinions have faithfully applied that requirement, other cases appear more adventuresome. In Dubroff II, the court found that the alleged facts supported an inference that three otherwise unaffiliated investors had acted as a controlling shareholder by engaging in a series of transactions that had enriched them at the expense of the minority shareholders and by “work[ing] together to establish the exact terms and timing” of the challenged recapitalization. In Frank v. Elgamal, plaintiffs survived a motion to dismiss by alleging members of the allegedly controlling group were united in entering into three agreements, despite having no voting agreement or common ownership. Relying on Frank, Hansen Medical held that allegations indicating coordination between the otherwise independent members of the supposed control group in previous transactions precluded dismissal where the members concurrently received benefits unavailable to minority shareholders in the contested transaction.
This phenomenon is troublesome, particularly if extended to putative groups of stockholder-directors. If several directors are “interested” in a transaction for purposes of § 144, then that has important implications for the standard of review. But assessment of those implications should not be oversimplified by lumping together those directors’ shares if they have no obligation to vote those shares uniformly. Delaware law generally regards share ownership by directors as useful, as it helps align the economic interests of directors with those of other stockholders. But the law should not reflexively deem a group of interested directors a controlling stockholder merely because they vote identically in one transaction.
Another troublesome issue arises where a court accepts the claim (at least for purposes of a motion to dismiss) that a person is a controller, with concomitant fiduciary obligations, despite owning no shares of stock at all. To be sure, if a non-stockholder that exercises control through ownership of or managerial authority over a parent entity uses that control to exercise voting or managerial control of a subsidiary entity, that non-stockholder takes on fiduciary duties to the controlled subsidiary. Our concern, however, is that the amorphous concept of “soft power” not arising out of stock ownership could be applied to trigger the entire fairness standard and preclude dismissal, where the premise of control involves circumstances that reflect garden variety commercial dealings, such as “the exercise of contractual rights to channel the corporation into a particular outcome by blocking or restricting other paths, . . . the existence of commercial relationships that provide the defendant with leverage over the corporation, such as status as a key customer or supplier, [or] [l]ending relationships, [which] can be particularly potent sources of influence.” The courts should heed doctrinal guardrails against overuse of this “soft power” concept: “authority [that] takes the form of a contractual right . . . must give the nonstockholder power akin to ‘operating the decision-making machinery of the corporation’ (a ‘classic fiduciary’), rather than ‘an individual who owns a contractual right, and who exploits that right,’ forcing a corporation to ‘react’ (which does not support a fiduciary status).”
Perhaps most important, pressures by plaintiffs to characterize defendants as controlling stockholders when they possess far less than majority ownership, and even unaffiliated defendants as a “situational control bloc,” could be reduced by returning to a robust recognition of the cleansing effect of informed independent director or stockholder approval. Interested transactions would not consequently receive starkly different treatment solely because the interested party defendants are characterized as a control group.
C. The Related Temptation to Expand the Definition of Self-Dealing Transactions
Renewed recognition of the cleansing effect of informed independent director or stockholder approval would solve a separate and increasingly difficult classification problem: determining when a non-ratable benefit to a corporate fiduciary triggers entire fairness review. Non-ratable benefits come in many varieties: severance benefits for management, officer or director positions in the surviving corporation, different liquidity desires even in a pro rata transaction, a higher price for a class of stock with admittedly far greater value because of its voting control, an opportunity to acquire an equity interest in the acquiring company, and elimination of potential derivative claims, to name just a few.
Like the pressure to characterize interested parties as controllers, MFW creep encourages plaintiffs to argue that non-ratable benefits to a fiduciary that accompany otherwise third-party transactions constitute a conflict of interest that triggers entire fairness review. There is precedent supporting this position, and we agree that a non-ratable benefit can require application of the entire fairness standard where (i) neither of the traditional cleansing mechanisms (independent director or stockholder approval) has been used and (ii) the fiduciary who received the benefit negotiated the main terms of the transaction and determined the allocation of the proceeds in a direct self-dealing manner.
But Delaware courts should be cautious about expanding the use of non-ratable benefits as a basis for expanding the scope of the definition of self-dealing transactions. Entire fairness review serves as a check on self-dealing, by requiring a party that essentially negotiated with itself to prove that what it received or gave constituted fair value. That function, however, is not implicated where a third party negotiates a merger with a company that has two classes of shares, and bargains over the price paid for each, and each class has a voluntary, informed class vote. Likewise, managers are entitled to contract for their future services and to receive fair compensation if they lose their job in a deal. Admittedly, it is problematic when directors or stockholders approve a transaction without realizing the existence of a non-ratable benefit to a fiduciary; but where that benefit is fully disclosed and approved, its recipient should not be required to disprove that it came at the expense of the corporation or the stockholders generally. Likewise, the fact that a controlled company makes a decision benefiting its parent should not invoke the entire fairness standard absent harm to the corporation or the minority stockholders. Controllers should not have to pay rents to the minority to, for example, conduct business in a tax efficient manner. So long as the controller does not extract value from the minority, there is no proper basis for fairness review to apply. In sum, we submit that invoking the business judgment rule based on use of any of the traditional cleansing protections would normalize and rationalize the judicial treatment of transactions involving non-ratable benefits to a fiduciary.
More generally, we believe, as with duty of care claims, any plaintiff arguing that a non-ratable benefit was a breach of the duty of loyalty should have to prove breach and resulting damages. The entire fairness standard should not be wheeled out to address these kinds of cases in an awkward and confusing way. So long as the plaintiff has the chance to prove a breach of this kind (e.g., that none of the protective devices was used with credibility or that the recipient fiduciary engaged in bad-faith overreaching) and damages (harm to company and other stockholders), a more than adequate deterrent exists.
D. Undermining Aronson’s Important Second Prong and Creating Inconsistent Assumptions About the Ability of Independent Directors to Make Impartial Decisions
The Delaware Supreme Court recently affirmed a ruling in which the Court of Chancery concluded that the two-prong demand requirement test articulated in 1984 in Aronson v. Lewis is “no longer a functional test,” and that demand can be excused only by demonstrating that a majority of directors face a claim of liability not exculpated by a charter provision under § 102(b)(7). Although we have no quarrel with the result reached in the case (dismissal), that approach precludes the use of the second prong of Aronson’s demand futility test to challenge self-interested transactions where the pled facts support an inference that a conflict transaction unfairly benefited an interested party and the independent directors acted with gross negligence (but not disloyalty) in approving it. That approach also thereby encourages courts to strain to infer bad faith on the part of such directors to avoid dismissing a loyalty claim against the interested party that would historically have satisfied Aronson’s second demand utility prong. Neither development is salutary, in our view. The treatment of Aronson in any event clashes with the inherent coercion rationale discussed above as the foundation for MFW creep, and the two doctrinal approaches cannot logically co-exist.
1. Why Post-Aronson Developments Did Not Warrant Abandonment of the Second Prong
The Delaware Supreme Court’s Zuckerberg opinion largely accepts the analysis of the Court of Chancery, and rests on the proposition that three developments in Delaware law post-dating Aronson made its second prong no longer a useful way to evaluate demand futility. For starters, Zuckerberg suggests that under Aronson merely pleading that the challenged transaction is one that would, as an initial matter, not be subject to the business judgment standard of review itself satisfies Aronson’s second prong, a suggestion that echoes the Chancery decision it affirmed. Second, the opinion explains away several cases decided in the wake of Aronson on the ground that § 102(b)(7) had not been enacted when they were decided. Finally, the court suggested that its decision in Cornerstone, holding that directors against whom no non-exculpated claim has been pled should be dismissed on a proper Rule 12(b)(6) motion even if non-exculpated claims exist against other directors (such as the interested party in a conflict transaction) was a further development undermining the rationale for Aronson’s second prong.
Building on these premises, Aronson’s second prong was seen as somehow too easy to satisfy—because it was triggered solely by pleading an initial standard of review, not particularized facts supporting an inference of ultimate breach (premise one)—and not fitting a world where independent directors can be dismissed under Rule 12(b)(6) if they only face an exculpated due care claim (premise two). The solution to this perceived problem was to abandon the second prong and essentially have the rule of Rales v. Blasband govern all demand cases, thereby requiring a showing that a majority of the demand board face a non-exculpated claim or are not independent from the interested party. The universal demand excusal test thus became the following:
- whether the director received a material personal benefit from the alleged misconduct that is the subject of the litigation demand;
- whether the director would face a substantial likelihood of liability on any of the claims that are the subject of the litigation demand; and
- whether the director lacks independence from someone who received a material personal benefit from the alleged misconduct that is the subject of the litigation demand or who would face a substantial likelihood of liability on any of the claims that are the subject of the litigation demand.
Under this test, if Aronson’s second prong was to be preserved at all, a plaintiff could only satisfy it by pleading particularized facts supporting a non-exculpated claim against the demand board majority. In our view, that approach eradicates the historical function of Aronson’s second prong as a safety valve. Although a rational policy choice, discussed below, can be made in favor of that approach, such an important new policy shift cannot be justified on the grounds that intervening developments have made Aronson’s second prong, as originally intended to be applied, of no continuing utility.
Beginning with the first of the three developments summarized above, we believe that the purpose of the second prong was never about pleading an initial standard of review; rather, it required pleading facts supporting an inference of an ultimate breach of duty. Aronson’s second prong explicitly calls on the Court of Chancery to inquire into “the substantive nature of the challenged transaction and the board’s approval thereof.” This means that a plaintiff cannot plead demand excusal under the second prong simply by noting that the transaction, as an initial matter, is subject to entire fairness review. To the contrary, the second prong has often been found not satisfied when that standard initially applied. If, for example, a special committee of independent directors approves a conflict transaction, and the plaintiff cannot plead particularized facts suggesting that the special committee process was tainted by some wrongdoing (e.g., fraud on the committee by the interested party or gross negligence by the special committee), then demand is not excused. The second prong requires pleading particularized facts that supports a pleading stage inference that an ultimate breach of fiduciary duty occurred. That goes well beyond pleading an initial standard of review. Thus, properly applied, there is not a danger that the second prong of Aronson easily allows a plaintiff to usurp a board’s presumptive authority to control the company’s claims. The rigorous requirement to plead particularized facts to support a rational inference of ultimate breach assures that is not the case.
As for the second and third developments that supposedly undermined Aronson’s second prong, we do not believe that the Delaware courts applied Aronson’s second prong for over thirty years without considering the impact of the enactment of § 102(b)(7) in 1986, and the longstanding potential for due care exculpation should have no bearing upon the continued utility of Aronson’s second prong. Delaware’s corporate bar readily understood that § 102(b)(7) created situations where approving an interested transaction could result in monetary liability of the interested directors, but not of independent directors acting in the good-faith belief the transaction was fair to the corporation. Likewise, Cornerstone was not a seismic change in practice under § 102(b)(7), as it was hardly the first case to recognize that individual directors not subjected to a non-exculpated claim should be dismissed and not have to remain as defendants just because other defendants face non-exculpated loyalty claims. In sum, no case law or legislative developments after Aronson warranted abandoning its important second prong.
2. Rales Should Not Displace Aronson’s Second Prong Because the Contexts of the Two Cases Differ
It is also significant that the Zuckerberg decisions, which stress the functional similarities between the Rales test and the Aronson test, overlook what is different about the context in which Rales applies—namely, when at least a majority of the board that would receive a demand is different than the one that made the decision that is the subject of the complaint. That is, Rales applies when a board either in whole or at least in majority is not asked to cause the company to sue someone over a decision that they had made. Delaware law has often looked to whether an independent board majority exists in terms of the deference it affords a decision, an approach resting on the sound intuition that when the independent directors have voting control of the boardroom they have more freedom for impartial action. The different test in Rales is explained by the demand board’s different responsibility for the transaction under litigation challenge and its effect on the board’s ability to consider a demand.
This difference has important implications in the history of and rationale for Aronson’s second prong. Aronson was decided at a time when the concept of an “independent director” was still nascent, and when there was debate about whether the concept had meaning. Some felt that the natural relationship of fellow directors created a structural bias, and that led to skepticism that even putatively independent directors could impartially decide whether to sue a fellow director. Aronson took note of this debate and the second prong helped to ameliorate this concern by giving a plaintiff two routes to demand excusal. The first was to plead that a majority of the demand board had ties to the interested party that compromised their ability to consider a demand to sue. But even if a plaintiff could not satisfy that first route, Aronson’s second prong gave the plaintiff a chance to get a merits adjudication by pleading particularized facts supporting an inference that the demand board had made a decision that involved a breach of fiduciary duty. When a plaintiff made this difficult showing, Aronson’s intuition was that demand should be excused because it was difficult to presume credibly that a board could sue the interested parties to a transaction the demand board had approved. Aronson thus took into account both the reality of how difficult it is to sue a fellow director (structural bias) and that suing someone else over a decision that you also approved is at the very least exceedingly awkward and involves some degree of hypocrisy. Without addressing this rationale, and the difference between the contexts of Aronson and Rales, Zuckerberg eliminated the historical function of Aronson’s second prong as a safety valve.
3. The Conflicting Rationales of Zuckerberg and Cases Extending the Reach of MFW
The Zuckerberg opinions also create a stark contradiction with the inherent coercion rationale underlying what we call MFW creep. The Chancery decision took the view set forth in EZCORP that a transaction with a controller cannot be subject to business judgment rule review unless the full suite of MFW protections is used. For the abandoned transaction that Chancery focused on, that did not occur. As important, Chancery found that the pled facts supported an inference that a special committee member faced a disloyalty claim for engaging in friendly communications with Mr. Zuckerberg that helped him in his negotiations with the special committee. Furthermore, Chancery found that the pled facts suggested that the special committee was not assertive in responding to Mr. Zuckerberg’s proposal, and the resulting transaction they approved was not fair to Facebook. Thus, the Court of Chancery clearly found that the particularized facts supported an inference that Mr. Zuckerberg and one special committee member had breached their fiduciary duty of loyalty, and that the special committee had failed to assure fair terms. Thus, although EZCORP presumes that even a properly motivated and assertive special committee cannot effectively check a controller and invoke the business judgment rule, Zuckerberg takes the view that the same directors who approved the challenged transaction can make the more difficult decision to cause the company to sue the controller (and the special committee member alleged to have cast his lot with the controller).
We respectfully submit, however, that this approach to Aronson ignores the continuing utility of Aronson’s second prong as an integrity-enhancing safeguard. Properly applied, Aronson’s second prong allows a plaintiff to plead facts suggesting that, despite the presence of a majority of independent disinterested directors and the use of facially adequate procedures, there was a fiduciary breach resulting in harm to the company. This safety valve exists precisely because of the potential for structural bias where (contrary to the assumption underlying Rales) a majority of the demand board approved the business decision under attack in the derivative action. At the same time, by precluding claims, never presented to the board for consideration, when the plaintiff cannot meet either of its two tests, Aronson avoids burdening stockholders with the systemic costs of litigation and judicial second-guessing of matters on which elected directors, not courts, have the ultimate say.
4. The Effect of Abandoning Aronson’s Second Prong
In most conflict transaction cases, the independent directors fulfill the important role of acting as a proxy for third-party bargaining. If the well pled facts support an inference that they failed to fulfill that role, not because of conscious disloyalty but because they did not act with due care, then their actions should have no cleansing effect and entire fairness review should apply. That situation is the one the second prong was designed to address, giving effect to the intuition that even where a board majority is independent of an interested party, structural bias might make it difficult for the directors to sue a colleague. That intuition also accords with Delaware cases recognizing that it is easier to say no to a colleague on a conflicted transaction than to sue him.
The Delaware Supreme Court suggested in Zuckerberg that the well-reasoned decision by Chancellor Chandler in McPadden v. Sidhu was an outlier. We respectfully disagree: McPadden gave traditional and literal effect to Aronson’s second prong. In that case, the company had sold a subsidiary to an officer for $3 million. Two years later the officer sold the subsidiary for $25 million. The plaintiffs alleged that the independent directors had breached their fiduciary duties by failing to oversee a proper sale process, by allowing the officer himself to conduct the sale process despite knowing he was an interested bidder, and then approving the sale to him at the low end of the valuation range. Finding that the particularized pled facts supported a non-exculpated claim against the officer that his loyalty breach was facilitated by the other directors’ gross negligence, the court denied the motion to dismiss under Aronson’s second prong, but dismissed the independent directors against whom no non-exculpated claim was pled under Rule 12(b)(6), leaving the officer who faced a non-exculpated loyalty claim as the sole defendant.
Although the Delaware Supreme Court acknowledged in Zuckerberg that McPadden was “understandable . . . given the plain language of Aronson,” it did not follow that plain language. Instead, the court abandoned the McPadden approach, finding that the second prong of Aronson is not satisfied unless the plaintiff pleads facts showing that a majority of the directors face a non-exculpated claim. This implies that a special committee or independent board majority can impartially consider a demand to sue the controller over a transaction that the committee or board majority had approved in a grossly negligent manner. At the same time, however, the law as articulated in EZCORP and other recent Chancery decisions presumes that independent directors are not capable of standing up to a controller and acting as an effective countervailing negotiating and approval authority in a conflict transaction. The resulting conflict of views about the capability of independent directors leaves Delaware law taking the Kafkaesque position of allowing allegedly careless directors to block a lawsuit over a transaction that would otherwise be unfailingly subject to judicial review for substantive fairness.
5. Creating Incentives to Characterize Director Conduct as in Bad Faith
Another drawback of Zuckerberg’s elimination of Aronson’s second prong is that it pressures well-meaning trial judges to excuse demand by inferring that independent directors with no apparent motive to be disloyal consciously abetted overreaching by an interested party. A recent case In re CBS Corp. adopted that approach, holding that demand was excused because the members of the special committee who negotiated and approved the transaction, despite being independent from the controller, were subject to a claim of disloyalty because their efforts were considered ineffective and their acceptance of some of the controller’s demands that they had earlier rebuffed suggested conscious wrongdoing. Remarkably, this decision came soon after a decision refusing to dismiss a claim that the same transaction was unfair to the stockholders of the other party to the merger. In both decisions, the special committee defendants failed to win dismissal despite having qualified advisors, a lengthy process, and no apparent disloyal motive, because the merger—a zero sum transaction—was, as a matter of pled facts, so unfair to both companies (simultaneously) as to permit an inference that the special committee members were not just grossly ineffective, but also conscious facilitators of unfairness.
The incentives created under Zuckerberg’s new reading of Aronson to question the motives of independent directors in this fashion and subject them to claims of disloyalty are troublesome because that exposure to litigation and reputational damage would give any rational director reason to be cautious about serving on a special committee. It is one thing for a court to infer that a special committee without ties to a controller, and with qualified advisors, fell short of the mark in securing a fair transaction. It is quite another thing for the law to put the onus on the court to infer knowing complicity by the independent directors, just to ensure the interested party is held accountable. Under the traditional and literal reading of Aronson, this perverse incentive did not exist.
The better way to address the potential for meritless litigation and to restore coherence to doctrine is not to undermine the credibility-reinforcing role of Aronson’s second prong. Rather, the business judgment rule principles upon which Aronson rested should be reinvigorated to give appropriate effect to the traditional protective devices, and to then use the second prong to permit cases to proceed where a plaintiff can plead with particularity a non-exculpated claim against any defendant. That result would require acknowledging that McPadden was correctly decided but would not require doctrinal contortion: the court could simply add a fourth element to the three-part demand futility test it adopted in Zuckerberg, excusing demand where the well-pled facts indicate that a majority of the directors acted with gross negligence in approving a transaction with a controlling stockholder.
6. Accepting Zuckerberg’s Policy Choice Requires Rejecting the Resurgence of the Inherent Coercion Doctrine
Zuckerberg represents at bottom an important new policy choice of Delaware’s corporate common law and cannot be rationalized on the ground that the logic of Aronson’s second prong has somehow been undermined by developments since the case was decided. As we have shown, that is not so, and properly understood, Aronson’s second prong acts as a check on structural bias by recognizing the difficulty directors have in suing a colleague over a decision the same directors approved in the first place and requiring a judicial adjudication of a breach of fiduciary duty claim when the plaintiffs can meet a higher particularized pleading standard demonstrating a rational inference of an ultimate breach of duty causing harm to the company. This balance, requiring plaintiffs to make a stronger showing than required to survive a Rule 12(b)(6) motion, but then excusing demand so that a claim that meets that demanding pleading requirement can be decided by a court on its merits, rather than gated by the board that approved the very decision under challenge, is one that remains a rational way to ensure the integrity of Delaware corporate law, while not undermining the principle that in most situations the board determines whether a corporation brings a claim belonging to the corporation.
If Zuckerberg is to be justified as a stable doctrine, then it must rest on acceptance of the actual policy choice that underlies it, which is that if a majority of the directors who approved a transaction that particularized facts suggest was tainted by a breach of fiduciary duty do not themselves face a risk of monetary liability, they can impartially decide to cause the company to sue the interested parties who do face that risk. That is a policy decision that no change in intervening law requires to have been made and represents instead a belief that even when making the most difficult decision a director could make—to sue a fellow fiduciary over a transaction that the independent director approved in the first instance—Delaware law presumes impartiality.
Although we favor the balance struck by Aronson’s second prong, we recognize that Zuckerberg’s different policy choice is defensible given the multiple accountability forces that work to hold corporate boards faithful and independent directors in particular vigilant. But, if Zuckerberg’s policy direction is to be embraced, it must be embraced in a coherent manner. We have no doubt that it is much easier for a parent or friend to discourage a young adult from smoking a joint when that is illegal, or from drinking and driving before they engage in that behavior, than it would be to turn that young adult in to the police if they failed to heed the warning. And if the parent or friend condoned the behavior in the first instance, we think it even more doubtful that they could decide impartially to report the violation to the police.
Delaware law has previously recognized that for directors, it is therefore easier for them to act as a check on wrongdoing or overreaching in the first instance, and thus to say no to a self-dealing transaction as a member of the special committee if the terms are not fair, than it would be to sue a fellow fiduciary over a transaction after the fact, especially given that they had approved that transaction in the first place. For these reasons, if Zuckerberg is to form a durable part of a coherent body of corporate law, restricting Lynch’s inherent coercion concept, limiting the application of MFW to going private transactions, and permitting the use of any of the traditional protective provisions with fidelity to cleanse other interested transactions is necessary if the premises on which fiduciary duty law rests are to be consistent and rational. If independent directors who the particularized facts suggest approved an unfair transaction by ineffectively failing to check the interested party’s self-interest are presumed capable of impartially suing, then certainly independent directors advised by qualified advisors should be presumed capable of effectively negotiating for fair terms and their conduct should invoke the business judgment rule. If Zuckerberg signals the beginning of an alignment toward greater respect for the traditional protective measures and toward a confinement of MFW to its originally intended narrow function, then we view that development with more optimism. If, by contrast, Zuckerberg’s policy choice co-exists with MFW creep, then Delaware law will rest on contradictory assumptions about director conduct and will invite criticism for subjecting certain claims to tighter judicial review, while using a change in demand excusal law to render that review illusory in the important context of derivative claims.