The difference can be readily illustrated by thinking of corporate excess production and burning of hydrocarbons, and then comparing that overproduction to our personal burning of hydrocarbons—when driving our cars, for example. Corporate hydrocarbon burning (and sales, and use) risks climate catastrophe for the planet decades from now. And personal hydrocarbon burning, such as when I drive my car—and when you drive yours—has us individually contributing to global warming and to the risk of climate catastrophe decades hence.
But our time horizon is not the principal mechanism that induces us to risk climate catastrophe. The primary mechanism here is that neither the polluting corporation nor the gasoline-burning car driver absorbs the full costs of his or her own pollution. These costs are spread over society. So my driving harms the environment, but (1) my driving harms it only a small amount and (2) with almost no negative environmental impact to me. When too many of us do the same thing, however, (1) we collectively harm the environment and (2) I feel some of that overall impact. And when the corporation, even the large megacorporation, burns hydrocarbons, or finds them and refines them and sells them, it harms the environment, but the harms are spread over society generally and not borne primarily by the firm’s stockholders, its executives, or its employees.
The profits from the pollution are internalized, but not the costs. The convenience of my driving to work today is nice for me, whereas the pollution and the contribution to environmental degradation are not nice but borne by society overall, not by me alone. My time horizon is not what counts here; it’s my capacity to externalize the costs that counts.
More on this below. For now, keep in mind that the solutions to climate change problems depend greatly on whether we think these problems are due to stock market short-termism—a time horizon problem—or to externalization. The latter is not a time horizon problem; it extends over the long run and is not due just to short-run thinking. If the problem really were one of short-termism, then common solutions would be to accord executives more autonomy from stock markets, to tax stock market trading, and to encourage long-term ownership of stocks. But if environmental degradation and global warming are not due in any strong way to stock market short-termism, then these proffered remedies will fail.
Bottom-line: If we continue to erroneously blame stock market short-termism for the severity of these problems, our remedial efforts will be mistargeted.
B. DuPont, Environmental Toxicity, and the Long Term
Consider a company in a country that does not regulate environmental wrongs. The company destroys its local environment and makes considerable profit by selling its products elsewhere. The company profits but does not pay for its environmental degradation. Others, external to the firm, pay. The social costs are great, but the problem is not primarily caused by the company having a stunted time horizon. Much that is environmentally costly is miscategorized as short-termism, when it really arises from distorted incentives and a lack of corporate conscience.
A DuPont episode illustrates this result. Long seen by many as “one of the most distinguished of . . . U.S. corporation[s]” and a dedicated long-term organization that was lauded by corporate law judges for its long-term orientation and its respect for corporate constituencies, it was embroiled in one of the major environmental debacles of our time. For six decades—a very long term—DuPont discharged a highly toxic chemical into the environment when it made Teflon. The company knew of both the chemical’s danger and the human body’s inability to rid itself of the toxin. Yet it refused inexpensive abatement. Executives counted on keeping inculpating information from the public and the government. They did so for decades, as Roy Shapira and Luigi Zingales show and as the movie Dark Waters—named for how and where the toxins were hidden—dramatizes. DuPont’s long-term horizon did not stop it from polluting dangerously.
True, there’s typically a lag between a polluter’s act and the polluter getting caught; profits are immediate and the cost of getting caught comes later, as was so for DuPont. But this time horizon consideration should not obscure the fact that the pollution was primarily an externality: DuPont captured the benefits while others—external to DuPont—suffered the costs. A shareholder who held DuPont’s stock for the long term made money from DuPont’s sixty years of Teflon pollution, even though the company was caught. DuPont did not pollute because it was pressured by short-term hedge-fund activists seeking to push a cost deep into the future, nor distracted by traders ignoring the future, nor pressured to report good results in a single financial quarter; it polluted because its internal organizational conscience broke down. Its long-term pollution paid off for both short-term and long-term shareholders.
Rewarding whistleblowing and facilitating liability, even punitive liability in excess of the damage caused, are plausible cures for this externalization, as is better regulation to make being caught more likely; lengthening corporate time horizons is not.
* * *
My purpose here is not to prove that stock-market-driven short-term proclivities have never exacerbated pollution or fraud, but that they are unlikely to be the biggest contributors to global warming, excess methane, and spoliation of aquifers. These social problems often emanate from a misdirected and selfish shareholder orientation. One does not cure such problems of conscience and externalization of costs with a longer time horizon for the stockholders. One cures them by making the polluter pay, right away or at least eventually. Yet too much of the rhetoric of policymaking mistakenly aims to lengthen time horizons.
C. Environmental Degradation and Global Warming as Corporate Selfishness
The DuPont example can be generalized: Even firms that think solely about the long term can and will pollute, degrade the environment, and warm the planet as long as they selfishly prioritize their own benefits and do so by externalizing the social costs of their business. (And we citizens who drive our cars and fly planes to visit relatives or to do our jobs are not much different.) Integrated oil companies are among the most long-term-oriented companies on the planet, with planning departments projecting worldwide energy needs and oil field possibilities decades into the future. Making them think more long term is not an important climate cure because, first, they already do, and, second, the problem is not their time horizon but that polluters (including us, driving our cars) do not pay. Longer-term thinking will induce firms to take into account the costs that they themselves pay years hence for their own pollution or from changes in production costs and sales (if they do not do so already). But if the social harm is not so much the self-inflicted portion but the externalized portion—as it seems to be—then making firms think longer instead of shorter will not solve our climate change problem.
Corporate critics should stop reflexively blaming major corporate problems on short-termism, not just because it’s conceptually incorrect but because doing so leads us to misidentify the underlying problems and solutions. Even if every corporation operated for its own long-run benefit, bad corporate social behavior could and would persist, as long as corporations can externalize costs. The polluting corporation is a bad citizen but need not have a short-term outlook.
It is not surprising that those who have thought most about environmental degradation typically identify a carbon tax as the best means of addressing the problem—a tax on the volume of carbon that citizens and companies release into the atmosphere. Carbon taxes address externalities by making people and companies pay for the negative consequences of their actions. The payment normally should induce them to pollute less. This policy effort targets the selfishness problem (and hence might work), not the time horizon issue, which is the wrong target and won’t work.
D. The Financial Crisis
A housing bubble grew during the first decade of this century until, by the decade’s end, it burst and caused a worldwide financial crisis that threatened to turn into a great depression. The crisis unleashed political forces that still disturb the polity and the economy.
Influential analysts blamed corporate and financial short-termism as a core cause of this crisis. The government’s official Financial Crisis Inquiry Commission castigated banks’ short-term executive compensation systems as propelling it. SEC Chair William Donaldson likewise saw “one of the root causes” of the crisis to be “[t]he excessive focus by too many corporations on achieving short-term results.” Timothy Geithner, who eventually became Secretary of the Treasury, concluded that “[t]his financial crisis had many significant causes, but . . . [i]ncentives for short-term gains [from executive compensation] overwhelmed the checks and balances meant to mitigate the risk of excess leverage.” Empirical studies exist on both sides: some show that the duration of executive compensation had no impact on a financial firm’s vulnerability, while others detect a correlation between the two.
Few analysts, even those emphasizing short-term executive compensation as a root cause, would, when explaining the financial crisis, leave out weakened financial sector capital requirements, the rise of unregulated but risky banking, and other core causes having little to do with executive compensation. But adding short-termism to the list of major causes is a mistake, because the systemic financial problem being analyzed is not fundamentally one of time horizons but, again, one of externalities. Those who conjure up a powerful short-term driver here see executives taking risks with their bank’s solvency that those same executives would shun if the risks were played out within the duration of the executives’ compensation packages. If I’m paid based only on how high this year’s profits are, I’ll take excessive risks with next year’s profits, taking the chance that next year’s profits will be obliterated in a financial crisis. This is indeed a time horizon contribution to financial risk-taking. But overly focusing on this channel will lead policymakers to miss the broader externalization channel, which is the main target.
The basic financial problem inducing the crisis was that the costs of a bank’s failure were mostly borne by others outside the bank and the executive suite. The losers were not primarily the risk-taking bank, its shareholders, and its executives but were instead the government, the rest of the financial system, and, most importantly, the country’s workers and taxpayers—all interests external to the risk-taking banks.
The government lost first by backing up failing banks’ deposits through the government’s deposit insurance and then by bailing out sinking banks. And the economy then suffered when banks failed and were bailed out. But if the banks’ risk-taking paid off, and there had been no failure, the gains would have been garnered almost entirely by the bank’s shareholders and stock-compensated executives, all of whom would have won big. Heads, the executive wins; tails, the rest of us pick up most of the loss. The executives’ time horizon was less important than the distorted payoffs in theirs and their stockholders’ compensation.
Imagine that the banks’ executives were paid over the long run with company stock. If they ran their banks in a risky way that usually pays them a million dollars annually but inflicts a trillion-dollar loss on the economy once in a while, they would still be incentivized to take that bet—good for them most of the time, but very bad for the rest of us when it’s a losing bet. The bankers still would have incentives to take the risk because most of the time they would get the million-dollar payoff. The bank and the executives bear only a sliver of the costs.
The key incentive-based cure is to unlink bank executives’ compensation from the banks’ stock. (Conscience, better regulation, and public-spiritedness can help too.) Financial firms that paid their executives more in debt-like claims that the executives had to hold on to, such as fixed pension obligations (which did not rise if the bank did well but fell when the bank did badly), fared better during the crisis. That pay package incentivized bankers to take fewer risks. Conversely, banks with high stock-based executive compensation took more risk than was good for financial stability. This problem is one of incentive alignment, not of stretching the executives’ time horizons. The two differ, but, in too much thinking about short-termism, they are often confused and thought to be the same.
E. Long-Term Externalization
A popular perspective in some quarters is that the corporation’s discount rate is too high when it evaluates the costs of future harms that it causes. An immediate lawsuit for the corporation’s tortious harm is, in this view, valued appropriately. But the firm values too low a potential loss in a lawsuit a decade hence. It discounts the costs of that lawsuit by an interest rate notably higher than the benefit a firm would get at a later time. Dig down, however, and the reason for the higher discount for future damage comes from the rising chance that a later harm may be avoided or eliminated. Corporate liability may just disappear over time. The next paragraphs analyze why and how.
Imagine that the corporation releases a deadly toxin. If the damage were done in the short run, the firm would, let’s assume, be liable in an amount commensurate with the harm done. But if the harm is done deep into the future, the company’s disposition to reap the short-run gains incentivizes it to release the toxin. Only the directors’ and executives’ consciences stand in the way of short-term gain and long-term harm. But properly understood, the problem is that externalization increases over time and not that the corporate discount rate is inherently too high.
The long-term reasons why the firm could escape liability are several. First, the corporation may disappear, leaving no entity to pay, even if liability would have been clear; the perpetrators clear a profit and then “skip town.” Second, causality and responsibility fade with time. E.g., was the deadly mesothelioma decades later caused by the corporation’s original release of asbestos or by the victims’ subsequent tobacco smoking? And, third, liability is simply cut off when the statute of limitations runs out and thereby bars otherwise winning lawsuits.
A misanalysis of these scenarios would conclude that the firm’s short-term profits lead it to take long-term risks. But properly analyzed, these considerations (corporate disappearance, fading causality, and the statute of limitations) are operating not principally as a time factor but as an externalization mechanism. Each factor increases the probability that the firm will not be held responsible for the harms it caused. It’s not that the firm is diminishing the value of its own future profits.
Here’s how the mechanism works: If disappearance, via shutdown, bankruptcy, or merger, cuts off liability years hence, then that shutdown creates an uncompensated harm. It’s that failure to compensate—i.e., that the corporation does not have to pay—that incentivizes the firm to ignore the risk; the long term and the discount rate are not the operative factor diminishing liability and increasing externalization. Rather, it’s that over time, liability disappears. If causality becomes uncertain with time, then that uncertainty creates an uncompensated harm; again, time and an increasing discount rate are not the operative factors. Increasing externalization is. If the statute of limitations runs out, then the policy reasons for statutes of limitations induce the externalization of harms and not a too-high corporate discount rate. Once again, time is not the operative factor diminishing liability but a legal system that cuts off liability, allowing the firm over time to externalize more harm.
A related conceptualization: Analysts distinguish the social discount rate from the private discount rate. Private projects’ discount rates are determined by market forces, it’s said, but the proper social discount rate is lower—making future projects with a social dimension more valuable than the market accords them. These contrasting rates militate, I argue, not for making corporations more long term but for the public to act directly by promoting the desired activity or realigning firms’ incentives to deter the undesired activity. Inducing corporations to adopt the public rate would make them use the wrong rate for their market-based activities.
Another way to look at the social discount rate follows. The main rationale for a low future discount rate (which makes the future more valuable) is that intergenerational equity demands that future generations be treated with more respect. A future life, in this thinking, is as valuable as a contemporary life—making the proper discount rate zero. Similarly, the market’s discount rate does not value the benefits that future generations will obtain from a safer planet not afflicted with detrimental climate change. But properly analyzed, this intergenerational disparity is also an externality and not a matter of the corporation being too short term in the time horizon sense we’ve used in this article’s inquiry. Today’s generation externalizes harms onto a future generation because that future generation is not represented in today’s relevant market transactions. The cure for this externality is appropriate regulatory action that internalizes that externality. Indeed, the social discount literature aims primarily to inform the policymaker—the social planner in this economic lexicon—and does not aim to adjust the corporate discount rate.
The public decisionmakers—a well-informed, disciplined government—should act directly by taxing the undesired activity, subsidizing the desired activity, and regulating the market to get to where the social planner thinks we should be. But public decisionmakers are responsible to today’s public, not to tomorrow’s citizenry. The problem is our collective inability to induce a more desirable future by making the undesirable future more costly.
F. When Time Horizons Could Count
All this is not to say that time horizons play no role at all.
In truly short-term stock-market-based corporate action, the firm imposes the cost on others for a quick corporate benefit, but at a long-term cost to the corporation itself. If the long-term costs to the corporation exceed its own short-term profits (properly discounting to present value), then we indeed have a true time-horizon, short-term issue. If instead the firm and its stockholders benefit in the short and the long run, we have a social problem, but not a time horizon problem.
If pollution or financial risk-taking are undiscoverable for longer than the executive expects to be with the company, the self-interested executive has reason to tolerate the undetected pollution now that will diminish the company’s stock price later, when the wrong is discovered and finally fully priced into the stock. But is this problem emanating from stock market short-termism? While popular discourse ties this harm to executive stock options that are worth more now, this tie-in is largely incorrect. It’s not the stock market’s purported short-termism that exacerbates the problem. Any compensation structure that rewards the executive for current profitability, despite hidden costs, incentivizes the executive to push costs out into the future. The executive could pollute, pump up profits, and take a cash bonus this year, expecting to be gone from the firm when the problem is discovered and the firm finally pays up.
The pay structure is what needs fixing, not the stock market. In fact, stock-based compensation, if done well, is better than a cash bonus for the long- vs. short-term problem. If the payment is in stock that the executive must keep deep into the future, then the executive cannot benefit by pushing costs into that future. The stock’s value will suffer when the pollution is discovered—if, but only if, the enforcement machinery to internalize the externality is strong. Hence, the company’s shareholders—the stock market—has the incentive to keep the executive “on the hook” longer. Thus, more stockholder power (through a stockholder say on executive pay) can be better for the environment in this delayed discovery scenario.
Consider another apparent time horizon channel: Some executives feel pressured to meet this quarter’s numbers, so they put off resolving an environmental problem or postpone awarding employees a well-deserved raise. And, once they begin shortchanging employees and degrading the environment for this quarter, they get caught up in the bad behavior and fail to correct it in the next quarter. What once was a short-term action turns into a long-term problem.
Such a channel fits aspects of the 2001 Enron scandal: the executives scrambled to show good quarterly results and did so fraudulently, hoping that better business in the future would hide their doctoring of the books. But that better business never came, so they found themselves pushed to falsify earnings levels for several years, until they were caught.
But while this sequence could relate to distorted time horizons, it need not. First, what we need to know is whether the short-term-pressured executive acts in a way that is detrimental to the firm’s long-term good. Recall the DuPont sequence. DuPont polluted early and then kept polluting. The pollution seems to have been profitable for the company in both the short and the long run. If too few firms are reprimanded, prosecuted, or fined for their transgressions, the action that is interpreted as short-term beneficial to the firm but at a long-term cost to the firm is actually beneficial to the firm in both the short and the long run. Second, in some instances, fraud is a benefit for the executive but is costly to the firm; curing the problem would not come by lengthening the firm’s time horizon but by making the wrongdoing executive behave better.
Vivid scandals like Enron make it easier for us to imagine that executives’ short-run misdeeds are costly in the long run to the firm. In Enron’s case, they were. In DuPont’s case they were not. Many such misdeeds are, one suspects, never uncovered and never become public scandals. Such undiscovered misdeeds are, one supposes, profitable to the firm in the short run and not costly in the long run. Lengthening time horizons, if this indeed correctly surmises the lack of long-term costs, would fail to remedy the problem.
This can be seen by imagining 1,000 firms taking a short-term action that will gain $1 million for each of those 1,000 firms at the expense of outsiders, for a total gain of $1 billion. One of these thousand firms will be caught and, when caught, that firm will have to pay (via a degraded reputation or by fines) $50 million. From the perspective of the firm that gets caught, the action certainly looks to be short term—a $1 million short-term gain that costs the firm $50 million in the long run. But from a portfolio-wide perspective, the firms gain $1 billion overall for a total cost of $50 million. Or from each individual firm’s perspective, each gains $1 million in the short run, at a cost of a .001 chance of a $50 million loss—i.e., an expected loss of $.05 million for a gain of $1 million.
These are not short-term actions that are, in the aggregate, costly to the firms in the end.
* * *
The underlying problem in such cases is not so much the short-termism but the fraud, the externality, and the misbehavior. Fix the fraud, incentivize the firm and its executives to internalize the externality, and punish the misbehavior—and then the problem is reduced or eliminated. Altering the firm’s time horizons may well do no good.
G. Index Funds as Universal Owners
The explosive growth of index funds, which own some stock in all firms in the market (or at least some of each company in the underlying index), raises some analysts’ hopes that (i) these index funds can overcome the externality problem and (ii) that the index funds’ long-term nature will facilitate that cure. The index funds’ long-term incentives come from their ownership structure: the indexer buys a slice of the entire stock market (or at least of one of the common indices, such as the Standard & Poor’s 500). It never sells out a stock position, other than if the stock is removed from the index. Hence, the thinking might run, the index fund’s long-term nature will enable it to diminish public firms’ short-termism, from polluting, risking climate change, and inducing financial crises. Here, I show that the hoped for overcoming of the externality problem (item (i) in this paragraph’s first sentence) does not arise from the funds’ long-term incentives.
Since these funds own a slice of the entire stock market, their incentives come closer to those of the nation as a whole than any individual firm’s incentives. Here too, however, we need to separate analysis of externalities from analysis of time horizons. The optimistic academic analysts’ hopes are not coming from an expectation of changing the index funds’ time horizons. Their hopes arise instead from the funds’ incentives to internalize the externalities that individual firms generate, which become costs to other firms in the indexers’ portfolios. If another firm in the index fully bears the costs of the polluting firm’s externality, then the index fund and its investors make no profit. One firm gains, another firm loses. The hope that the indexers can fix the pollution, climate change, and financial risk-taking problems come not from the indexers’ long-term incentives but from their incentives to internalize their portfolio firms’ externalities.
Here’s what I mean: If the indexers fail (or do not try hard enough), is it because they are not long-term enough, or because they cannot successfully internalize the costs that their portfolio firms produce? It’s the latter, not the former. I elaborate next.
First off, index funds today own about 20 percent of the stock market. Although that is substantial, it is not a slice of the entire economy; hence, much of the economy is external to the index fund’s portfolio, which lowers the indexer’s incentive to internalize. Moreover, not every firm is in every index—several thousand public firms are not in the Standard & Poor’s 500, which is the base for multiple major index funds. And about half of the economy is in private firms. Internalizing externalities in public firms could benefit those private firms that no longer have to bear those externalities, meaning that the index fund bears a cost while other firms outside the index gain a profit. And those private firms, not subject to the index funds’ purported incentive to internalize the public firms’ harm-causing externalities, could pick up the profitable harm-causing activities that the index funds induce some public firms to forgo.
Furthermore, individuals often bear the costs of corporate externalities, from breathing polluted air or being subjected to excessive risks from corporate products. These costs are not borne by the index funds’ portfolio companies and, hence, will not readily be internalized by the index fund that thinks only of costs to its other portfolio firms. Financial panics also put unindexed firms’ viability and individuals’ jobs at risk; hence, there’s not enough for the index funds to internalize because business activities affect too many other economic actors whom the index funds have no financial incentive to save. And as for climate change, firms adversely affected by global warming are hurt, but individual well-being is hurt even more. The externality problem does not disappear; the problem that indexers face and that the optimists hope they can cure is not primarily a time horizon problem.
Second, the externality problem is even embedded inside the fund managers’ operations. A fund manager may sponsor and manage an index fund and an exchange-traded energy fund. The index fund’s incentives may become “green,” but its energy-based fund will pay a high price for that decision.
Third, even if the index funds had perfect incentives to internalize widely, other stockholders do not. Other stockholders could seek to externalize harms (they will call this profit-seeking and management improvement, not externalization of harms) and have incentives to reduce the index funds’ influence. The resulting conflict will use up economic resources. But, once more, it is conflict over externalization, not over time horizons.
H. System-Wide Corporate Short-Termism?
The environmental problem can be confused with long-term vs. short-term issues because the overall system does indeed burn up social resources in the short term at the expense of social well-being in the long term. When firms overconsume hydrocarbons for today’s profit, at the expense of long-term, civilization-threatening global warming, then society incurs a big cost in the long term. But the operative mechanism is that a firm profits from hydrocarbons, while it bears only a fraction of the resulting costs. The polluter does not pay enough. The corporation (like individuals who drive cars and pollute) is selfish, but it’s society that is functionally short term, not the car driver or the corporation.
Let’s consider this problem in extreme terms of catastrophic climate change. All corporate leaders may believe that catastrophe is probable, but each knows that a single firm’s actions cannot make a difference. Each thus releases methane and burns hydrocarbons (or sells them to us, and we burn them to heat our houses and run our cars). All of us suffer later. No single firm can make a difference in avoiding catastrophe.
Even the climate-worrying CEO could contribute to the catastrophe—“I alone cannot reduce the chance of catastrophe; I can only cut my modest contribution, which would slash my profits and still not avoid the catastrophe,” the CEO calculates. “If I could affect every firm, I could reduce the chance of catastrophic climate collapse thirty years hence. But I cannot affect every firm. Only the government or some other collective action can get this done right.”
Some stock-market-wide investors do admonish their portfolio companies to respect the environment and combat climate change. (Whether this rhetoric plays out positively on-the-ground is yet to be seen, but the rhetoric and for now the will are there.) But as we saw in Part G, the problem is much bigger than the index funds’ capacity to internalize the harms.
The socially distorted incentive of the individual free rider is why collective organization, usually government-organized or government-mandated or government-incentivized action (such as via a carbon tax), is needed to remedy this so-called “tragedy of the commons.” These are problems of individual firms offloading costs outside the corporation, of individuals polluting more than they should, and of countries around the world hoping that other countries will fix the problem.
I. Consequences
Overly attributing problems to stock market short-termism has consequences. First and foremost, we (analysts, policymakers, the public) thereby see more stock market short-termism than there really exists. Stock market short-termism seems then not to be a merely minor defect in the corporation, but a society-threatening, even civilization-endangering, debility.
Second, overly attributing social, economic, and climate problems to stock market short-termism distorts policymaking. That is, one might think the over-attribution problem could be disregarded. After all, externalities are bad and should be corrected. Excessive stock market short-termism is also bad. We would be better off without either. Both should be corrected and a cost-effective way of doing so needs to be implemented. If political leaders use shortcuts and simple phrases to criticize the problem, well, that’s acceptable, one might say. They need to speak to the average voter, not to the climate scientist.
But when short-termism seems broader than it is, there’s more justification for pouring resources into diminishing it. When we mix externalities with true short-termism, the remedies are mixed and become garbled. Policymakers believe that by lengthening corporate time horizons they can seriously reduce global warming.
Some of this mistaken thinking may have been at the root of recent European Union initiatives on corporate governance. These initiatives sought to reduce shareholder authority over executives who are grappling with climate degradation. One can understand why policymakers become misguided in this way. These misconceptions allow them to believe that solutions to climate change can be had without any budgetary impact. Policymakers reduce the influence of shareholders, raise the power of directors and executives, and convince themselves and voters that they—the policymakers—have moved a powerful pro-climate, anti-global-warming policy initiative forward. This misguided action provides an illusion of positive movement. It saves the political leader from raising taxes on carbon—gasoline taxes at the pump have never been popular and for a political leader to seek to raise gasoline taxes is a good way to lose votes—and from making hard choices between and among nuclear, wind, and other sources of electrical power.
Conclusion
Society, when dealing with persistent externalities, is overall short term and foolish, while individual firms are selfish, but not short term.
Environmental degradation, global warming, shoddy products, financial crises, mistreated employees, and severe inequality are among the most severe problems we face as a society. If we blame stock market short-termism for these societal problems—when they instead emanate primarily from corporate selfishness and a lack of political will to deal with the problems directly—then policymakers will try to cure these serious problems by lengthening the stock market’s time horizon or insulating executives from the stock market. But lengthening the stock market’s time horizon will not fix these problems because they are for the most part not time horizon problems. This mistaken targeting pulls policymakers away from sounder efforts, such as a carbon tax to address climate change or better regulation to keep banks well-capitalized and safe. Mistakenly thinking that one can ameliorate environmental degradation and avoid financial crises by curing stock market short-termism means that we will have more environmental degradation and risk more deeply damaging financial crises before solutions are found.