Bork conveniently omits from his reasoning any actual or potential rivals to the manufacturer. Even though the basic concern with a dominant manufacturer purchasing retailers is the foreclosure of rival manufacturers, Bork relies on an economic model in which that concern cannot arise because there are none. If one expands the model to include rival manufacturers, foreclosure can easily occur. A bit later, Bork mentions the theory that entry may be deterred if a new firm must enter at both the manufacturing level and the retail level, but he summarily dismisses this perfectly valid theory by stating without evidence that “the effort to block entry in this manner will surely prove both costly and fruitless.”
Bork’s book is a full of faulty arguments that follow this same structure: rely on an overly simple economic model and then misuse that model to reach broad antitrust policy conclusions that are biased against antitrust enforcement. Examples include his assertion that price cutting “does not provide a likely means of predation,” his claim that placing restrictions on “any firm size created by internal growth,” regardless of the tactics used to grow, will with “high probability” be harmful, and his argument that exclusive dealing “creates efficiencies and does not create restriction of output.”
The approach taken by Bork and other Chicago School lawyers would not withstand peer review, for two basic reasons. First, fragile conclusions based on very simple models are not reliable for policy recommendations. The Chicago School lawyers never checked the robustness of the simple models upon which they were relying, and they lacked the tools to do so. Second, and directly contrary to what Chicago School economists proudly stood for, the Chicago School lawyers based their dramatic policy conclusions on little or no systematic empirical evidence.
The advances in IO Economics during the 1970s and 1980s did not support the laissez faire approach to antitrust that we now associate with the Chicago School. There was no empirical finding that predatory pricing is rare or theoretical result that predatory pricing is irrational. There was no empirical or theoretical finding that all vertical mergers are procompetitive, and economic theory teaches otherwise. There was no empirical finding that exclusive dealing provisions used by a firm with substantial market power typically promote competition, and economic theory warns otherwise. Much of this was clear to many economists in the 1980s, and indeed starting in the 1980s a steady stream of “Post-Chicago” publications appeared.
Yet Bork’s cavalcade of errors still matters today because the courts have often adopted his reasoning and cited his work, and because similar errors have been propagated by other Chicago School lawyers. Put simply, these lawyers and their followers have successfully embedded into antitrust case law a series of propositions that were never established empirically and were never valid as a matter of economic theory in the first place. Jonathan Baker has identified a number of erroneous arguments put forward by the Chicago School using these tactics: markets self-correct through entry; markets self-correct because oligopolies compete and cartels are unstable; monopolies innovate; monopolists cannot obtain more than a single monopoly profit; and business practices prevalent in competitive markets cannot harm competition.
Based on this distorted view of how markets operate, and freed from the strictures of sound economic analysis, Chicago School lawyers convinced the courts to erect greater and greater hurdles to antitrust plaintiffs, dramatically weakening antitrust enforcement, under the false pretense that they were bringing sound economics to the law. As a leading example, Frank Easterbrook undermined antitrust enforcement under cover of purportedly neutral “error cost” analysis. Easterbrook’s entire analysis was based on an economic assumption he made that “Monopoly is self-destructive. Monopoly prices eventually attract entry.” But his assumption that monopoly power erodes soon enough was based on ideology, not evidence. Then and now, IO economists understand that monopolies can last for a long time, especially (and ironically) if antitrust enforcement is as lax as Easterbrook favors. Easterbrook mirrors his economic assumption with a legal one: “If the court errs by condemning a beneficial practice, the benefits may be lost for good.” His assumption that erroneous condemnations are rarely if ever corrected was demonstrably false in 1984 and dramatically so today given how antitrust law has evolved. During the decade just before Easterbrook wrote his article, antitrust case law had been evolving rapidly, leading a number of older, pro-plaintiff cases to be narrowed or overruled.
After stacking the deck, Easterbrook argued that antitrust courts should err on the side of defendants, because “judicial errors that tolerate baleful practices are self-correcting, while erroneous condemnations are not.” Like Bork, Easterbrook achieved his desired result based not on economic theory or empirical evidence, but by making strong and unjustified assumptions.
I do not mean to suggest that the Chicago School has run the table over the past 40 years. There are certainly many sound antitrust decisions that rely on IO Economics, and even an occasional decision by the Supreme Court in favor of antitrust plaintiffs. But plaintiffs in antitrust cases now face undue burdens in many cases as a result of Chicago School arguments that have been deeply embedded into the case law, especially as regards unilateral conduct.
Before discussing how we can fix this problem, it is worth noting that the story relating to cartels and horizontal mergers is quite different from that relating to monopolization and vertical practices. In other words, the story regarding coordination and collusion is very different from the story regarding exclusion. By and large, the Chicago School lawyers have supported vigorous antitrust enforcement against cartels, and antitrust law has been steadfast in condemning them. And horizontal merger enforcement has followed quite a different path, in part because the Supreme Court has not ruled on a horizontal merger in decades.
For horizontal mergers, IO Economics has greatly influenced agency enforcement and the development of the case law over the past 60 years. Back in the 1950s and 1960s, the SCP framework animated a generalized concern among IO economists about market concentration. The SCP framework lay behind the structural presumption that the Supreme Court articulated in 1963 in Philadelphia National Bank. The primary antitrust concern with horizontal mergers during that era was what we now call “coordinated effects,” which were the focus of the SCP framework. The SCP framework also provided the intellectual foundation for the 1968 Merger Guidelines. While the market concentration thresholds went up markedly in 1982, and then more in 2010, market concentration remains a central element of horizontal merger analysis.
Over the past 50 years, the antitrust treatment of horizontal mergers has incorporated many aspects of new learning from IO Economics, most notably by including and elevating the role of unilateral effects in merger analysis and by giving greater consideration to innovation effects. I attribute this in large part to the influence of the Horizontal Merger Guidelines, first issued in 1968, and to the significant role played by economists at the DOJ and the FTC. Nonetheless, the Chicago School influence can be felt in the area of horizontal mergers. The courts erected higher hurdles that the government must surmount to establish its prima facie case, weakened the structural presumption, became overly receptive to the entry defense, and required the government to do more to prove that a proposed remedy—usually behavioral—would not be adequate. These obstacles to horizontal merger enforcement have become more problematic as evidence has mounted that mergers have harmed competition in some sectors of the economy.
Restoring Effective Antitrust Enforcement
In this section I sketch out how antitrust law can shed itself of Chicago School ideology unsupported by economics to adopt a Modern vision for the Future of Antitrust.
I confine myself here to antitrust enforcement, which is but one part of competition policy. For a broader discussion of competition policy in the years ahead, including regulation, see Restoring Competition in the United States: A Vision for Antitrust Enforcement for the Next Administration and Congress.
Protecting and Promoting Competition. My discussion in this section takes as a given that the goal of antitrust is to protect and promote competition. I revisit that below when I address Populist proposals to broaden antitrust’s goals.
The courts commonly address whether a merger or challenged conduct is procompetitive or anticompetitive. Under current case law, this assessment is often made by applying the “consumer welfare standard.” That term has outlived its usefulness and should be retired. I advocate replacing the term “consumer welfare standard” with the term “protecting competition standard” to make clear that the goal of antitrust is to protect and promote competition. This proposal involves a change in language, not a substantive change in the goal of antitrust law. Here is my definition of the protecting competition standard:
A business practice is judged to be anticompetitive if it harms trading parties on the other side of the market as a result of disrupting the competitive process.
By the “competitive process,” I mean the dynamic process by which market participants seek to grow by offering more attractive terms and conditions to those with whom they trade. Disrupting the competitive process can involve blocking rivals by impeding their ability to make attractive offers to customers as well as short-circuiting competition by colluding with or merging with rivals. A firm does not disrupt the competitive process by taking an action that makes its offerings more attractive and does not block its rivals from competing on the merits.
I favor this change in language because the term “consumer welfare standard” has become confusing and counterproductive. Understanding how that happened is instructive.
During the middle of the 20th century, the courts struggled to distinguish business behavior that was a legitimate form of competition from behavior that harmed competition. The courts eventually came to understand one of the basic principles of IO Economics: many forms of legitimate competition harm rivals but benefit customers. In the canonical situation, a firm that lowers its price or improves the quality of its products harms its rivals and benefits its customers. Indeed, that is a fundamental property of competition to serve customers. In that context, the term “consumer welfare standard” usefully directed attention away from the impact of such business practices on rivals and toward their impact on customers. For the same reason, antitrust developed the mantra that “antitrust protects competition, not competitors.”
Unfortunately, the term “consumer welfare standard” never did a good job conveying the deeper underlying idea of protecting and promoting competition. To see why, consider a merger between two large employers that harms workers by creating or enhancing employer buyer power in a local labor market. This merger lessens competition among employers for workers and thus is a problem under the “protecting competition standard.” But a sensible person might well query whether the merger is a problem under the “consumer welfare standard.” That term directs one’s attention toward consumers, which is a distraction in this example.
As a substantive matter, antitrust law understands that a merger can enhance market power on the buyer side and anticompetitive conduct can harm sellers, including workers. In my example, the local labor market would be a relevant market, and one concern would be enhanced power on the buyer side of that market, i.e., by employers. But the public can all too easily be left with the impression that antitrust is just about final consumers and ignores the interests of workers, farmers, or business customers. Why keep using a term that is so prone to misunderstanding?
A further problem with the term “consumer welfare standard” is that the courts have used it to impose additional burdens on antitrust plaintiffs to quantify consumer harm. That has led the courts in some cases to focus excessively on short-term price effects and discount longer-term effects on prices, product quality, or innovation that are harder to quantify. Naturally, merging parties respond strategically. For example, in the T-Mobile/Sprint merger case, the merging firms promised not to raise prices to consumers for three years, as though such a promise could turn an anticompetitive merger into a procompetitive one. In other cases, merging firms sign multi-year contracts with customers and then assert that these customers are protected so the merger should be allowed under the consumer welfare standard. That is dangerous. Under the “protecting competition standard,” attention would be directed less toward short-term price effects and more toward how the merger would alter competition.
Above all, the protecting competition standard, with its language about “disrupting the competitive process,” speaks more directly to the goal of antitrust and evokes market dynamics and innovation. Under the protecting competition standard, the claim that a monopolist can exclude a small rival because that rival is less efficient would fall flat.
Protecting Competition Using Existing Antitrust Statutes
The DOJ and the FTC can substantially influence the development of antitrust case law by using their authority and resources to persuade the courts to fashion legal rules that treat business practices based on their probable real-world economic effects, supported by accepted economic theory and reliable evidence, not based on outdated assumptions or laissez-faire ideology. If the DOJ and FTC are successful in this effort, I have some modest hope that, in time, the courts will reduce some of the obstacles to sound antitrust enforcement that are present today. Here, I give a flavor for how that can be done. I do not attempt to offer a comprehensive enforcement agenda.
Create Rebuttal Presumptions in Favor of Antitrust Plaintiffs
The courts could create more paths by which antitrust plaintiffs can establish a rebuttable presumption that certain conduct harms competition, reduce the quantum of proof required to establish these presumptions, and/or require defendants to present stronger evidence to rebut them. This type of “quick look” analysis would follow the three-step burden shifting framework that is familiar to antitrust lawyers. This approach would greatly focus and simplify antitrust cases. By building better economics into the law, the scope and complexity of the economic expert testimony in many individual cases would be reduced. I am betting that judges and litigating attorneys would welcome that!
Economics provides an indispensable way to sift through a mountain of evidence to better understand the likely economic effects of various business practices in comparison with some suitable counterfactual. Economics is not “pro-defense” or “pro-plaintiff.” Properly used, economics instructs us what to look for in a given case to assess effects. Economics is not about what can never happen. Those aiming to downplay the use of economics in antitrust confuse the role of economics in assessing economic effects with the distinct issue of how the courts have set legal standards and apportioned burdens of proof. In my examples below, I suggest building sound economics into the legal standard. That will strengthen antitrust enforcement, improve the accuracy of antitrust decisions, and simplify litigation.
Here are a few examples of some recent cases that would have been decided in a more plaintiff-friendly manner had the courts properly used economic theory and evidence and applied the protecting competition standard.
The Supreme Court would have adopted a rebuttable presumption against any large transfer of value from a branded pharmaceutical company to a potential generic entrant as part of their settlement of a patent infringement case. The burden would then shift to the defense to show that any such transfer of value was made for a purpose other than delaying generic entry. The plaintiff would not have to prove that the transfer of value is “unexplained.” This would be a very focused inquiry, simplifying these cases; there would be no need to define a relevant market. This approach is strongly supported by economic theory and overwhelming evidence that generic entry lowers prices.
The Supreme Court would have upheld the district court’s opinion in favor of the plaintiffs based on the factual finding that American Express’s no-steering rule disrupted the competitive process and elevated merchant acceptance fees by stifling price competition among credit cards for merchant acceptance. Those factual findings should have created a presumption that the rule was anticompetitive, which American Express failed to rebut.
This case illustrates how Chicago School ideology has displaced common sense and sound economics at the Supreme Court. Applying IO Economics, the Court would have started with deep skepticism about American Express blocking merchants from offering discounts on transactions that do not involve American Express. Yes, American Express should have the freedom to choose its own business model—high merchant acceptance fees and high rewards to cardholders. But that freedom does not extend to disrupting the ability of other payment systems to deploy their own distinct business models—lower merchant fees and lower rewards—especially if they threaten American Express by fomenting price competition. Instead, the Supreme Court went down a distracting and irrelevant rabbit hole relating to market definition.
The Ninth Circuit would have upheld the district court’s opinion based on the district court’s factual finding that Qualcomm’s no-license/no-chip policy had the economic effects of raising the costs of Qualcomm’s rivals (modem-chip makers) and raising the all-in price of modem chips to customers (manufacturers of cell-phones).
Something is deeply wrong with antitrust law when the facts show that a monopolist has engaged in conduct that excludes competitors by raising their costs and harms customers by raising prices, yet an appellate court does not see an antitrust violation. My reading of the Ninth Circuit opinion is that the appeals court had difficulty understanding the economic effects of Qualcomm’s no-license/no-chips policy, so it defaulted in favor of the defense. That instinct is very much in the Chicago School tradition.
The district court would have blocked this merger if stronger evidence were required to rebut the structural presumption. The district court would not have discounted Sprint’s ability to compete, given Sprint’s sizeable market share and its own market share projections. The district court would have required more convincing evidence of Sprint’s coming decline before accepting a speculative efficiency defense and a dubious, slow-acting remedy containing many conduct elements for years to come.
Many other areas of antitrust law would benefit from a recalibration in favor of plaintiffs, based on the current state of knowledge in IO Economics. To be clear: I am talking here about reducing the burden on plaintiffs for various types of conduct that already can be illegal under current antitrust case law. I generally favor the use of rebuttable presumptions rather than per se rules, but views on this differ among Modernists based on how they trade off accuracy vs. simplicity. To give a few more illustrative examples, presumptions against the following conduct by dominant firms are well worth considering: (1) acquisitions of significant actual or potential rivals; (2) open early/closed late strategies that exclude rivals; (3) below-cost pricing; and (4) exclusive dealing requirements imposed on important trading partners.
The evidence required to rebut these presumptions will vary from one practice to another. For example, a dominant firm might defend below-cost pricing by pointing out that selling one product below cost generates profit margins on a complementary product, so it was not actually losing money on the sales in question. That defense could apply if the dominant firm is offering a free service to consumers to generate advertising revenue or selling a piece of durable equipment to generate profitable aftermarket sales of parts and service. My point is that the burden would rest on the dominant firm to explain its below-cost pricing, not on the plaintiff to prove that entry barriers are sufficiently high that recoupment will be possible in the future.
Allow Plaintiffs to Prevail Without Defining a Relevant Market. The courts also can simplify antitrust cases and make fewer errors by giving more weight to direct evidence of the economic effects of challenged practices and providing more plaintiffs with a path to success that does not require defining a relevant market.
The courts could first look for direct evidence of economic effects. This evidence might be qualitative or quantitative. Alternatively, the courts could define a relevant market in situations where market shares are informative about economic effects. This is by and large what the DOJ and the FTC do in their investigations. If they see harmful effects, they can reverse-engineer a relevant market in which those effects are situated, as part of preparing to litigate cases where the courts will require them to define a relevant market.
For example, in horizontal merger cases, the courts could allow the government to establish a presumption of harm to competition by showing that the two merging firms are substantial, direct rivals, without the need to define a relevant market. This would not prevent the government from alternatively invoking the Philadelphia National Bank structural presumption, which remains well grounded in economic research, as large increases in market concentration caused by horizontal mergers tend to lead to a substantial lessening of competition.
IO economists know that the actual economic effects of a practice do not turn on where one draws market boundaries. I have been involved in many antitrust cases where a great deal of time was spent debating arcane details of market definition, distracting from the real economic issues in the case. I shudder to think about how much brain damage among antitrust lawyers and economists has been caused by arguing over market definition.
Both the Chicago School and the Populist camps use the technical step of defining the relevant market as a vehicle to achieve the results they want—less or more antitrust enforcement as the case may be—rather than seeking to assess economic effects directly.
The Chicago School emphasizes market definition because antitrust defendants often win by arguing that the plaintiff has not properly defined the relevant market. Defendants have managed to turn market definition into a gating item under the case law, even if there is direct evidence of anticompetitive effects. We see this in the American Express case, where the Supreme Court ruled in favor of the defendants based on the government’s failure to properly define the relevant market, despite the district court finding direct evidence of significant anticompetitive effects. This same tactic was used in the second Staples/Office Depot case where the defendants extensively cross-examined the FTC’s economic expert (me) on the relevant market and market shares, but studiously avoided the most significant economic evidence in the case, which showed that the merging firms were the two leading bidders in many procurements for office supplies by large businesses. In addition, after the relevant market has been defined, antitrust defendants often attempt to use market share metrics in an asymmetric way that favors them.
Similarly, the highly structural approach favored by the Populists as a means to deconcentrate the economy necessarily relies heavily on defining relevant markets and measuring market shares in a way that is intended to favor plaintiffs. The Populists gloss over major challenges posed by their very heavy reliance on market definition. A highly structural approach driven by market definition may end up making antitrust more arcane and detached from reality, as even more cases turn on how the relevant market is defined. Such a focus may make antitrust cases harder, not easier, for plaintiffs to win. Antitrust litigators know well that the more weight one puts on market definition and market shares, the more effort litigants will spend on those topics. Yet, as any economist will tell you, the economy is not partitioned neatly into various “relevant markets,” especially today, where products and services are highly differentiated. In many cases, emphasizing market definition instead of economic effects would draw attention away from the real story and to an arcane boundary-drawing exercise.
Take horizontal mergers—which I consider critical for antitrust enforcement. In my experience, the government needs to tell a convincing story of harm to the public to convince a federal judge to block a proposed merger. I suspect this will remain true even if the law were to change so that lower concentration levels would trigger a stronger structural presumption. In that world, if the government does not tell a textured, coherent story about how the merger will harm trading partners, it will still be at serious risk of losing. The loss just would come in the form of an unconvinced court rejecting the government’s relevant market, ruling that the government has not properly established the structural presumption. For this reason, I favor presumptions that are well connected to the underlying economic effects. The structural presumption based on the level of the HHI is well suited for mergers involving coordinated effects; the change in HHI and upward pricing pressure are well suited for mergers involving unilateral effects.
By way of contrast, the Modern approach seeks to more accurately assess economic effects using the best available methods. Antitrust law can do that by establishing rebuttal presumptions that certain categories of conduct often harm competition, calibrating the legal standards of proof to reflect economic reality, and then narrowing attention in individual cases to the most probative evidence of economic effects.
In summary, the Modernist vision for the Future of Antitrust under the current antitrust statutes is to vigorously challenge mergers and business conduct that harm counterparties by disrupting the competitive process, based on the best evidence of likely economic effects. That will require perseverance. Antitrust defendants are well-counselled and well-funded and they will not readily cede ground, especially if they believe they have precedent on their side and will receive a favorable hearing on appeal, not an unreasonable expectation given the current judiciary.
This state of affairs is unsatisfactory in many ways. Based on my experience in antitrust litigation, I fear that any progress along these lines will be painfully slow. So let me turn to . . .
Updating the Antitrust Statutes. Many observers, myself included, are unwilling to wait 30 to 40 years for antitrust to correct itself through the slow evolution of the case law. Plus, one can hardly be confident that the case law will move at all in the direction of stronger antitrust enforcement over the next decade or two, based on recent decisions by the Supreme Court and its current makeup. For these reasons, I support legislative changes that codify the approach supported by the Modernists. To that end, along with a group of experienced antitrust practitioners and academics, I endorsed the bill recently introduced by Senator Amy Klobuchar, the “Competition and Antitrust Enforcement Reform Act of 2021.” I applaud Senator Klobuchar’s efforts to strengthen horizontal merger enforcement and to overrule a number of faulty, pro-defendant Supreme Court cases involving conduct by large firms. For more details on the type of legislation that I support, see Restoring Competition in the United States: A Vision for Antitrust Enforcement for the Next Administration and Congress.
Even with new legislation, antitrust can and should only do so much. We very much need new sector-specific regulations, especially to deal with the tech titans. Article III courts are poorly suited to provide ongoing regulation of the terms and conditions on which one firm must deal with another, especially in the presence of rapidly changing technology. Plus, ex post antitrust enforcement is not a substitute for ex ante industrywide rules. As the rest of the world has realized, we very much need sector-specific regulation to reign in the power of the tech titans and to cure problems associated with the misuse of personal data and with the spread of misinformation. Many of the ills requiring regulation do not involve the abuse of market power. For now at least, the United States will be watching from the sidelines as the UK and the EU move forward to regulate core platform providers who are “gatekeepers” in digital markets.
The Populist Challenge to Antitrust
I now turn to address the Populists, who are often called Neo-Brandeisians.
My starting point is that I share many sympathies with the Populists. Like them, I am deeply concerned about the excessive political power of large corporations. Like them, I believe that today’s extreme levels of income and wealth inequality in America are very unhealthy for our democracy and for our society. Like them, I believe that the growing share of the economic pie going to shareholders and the declining share going to workers has contributed to this inequality. Like them, I believe that better public policies can go a long way to fixing these problems, if only we can find the political will to enact them. Like them, I believe that antitrust enforcement has been too lax, largely as a result of the durable influence of the Chicago School.
However, my assessment of what is causing these social and economic ills differs from the Populists’ assessment. We both read the accumulating economic evidence as showing that market power has risen in a number of sectors of the U.S. economy and that antitrust enforcement has generally been too lax. However, where the Populists see an economy infested with monopolists, I see an economy that is dynamic and competitive in many respects, but can and should be more so. I see grave problems with market power in the health care sector and a number of others, but I also see vigorous competition in large portions of the U.S. economy.
The Populists implicate lax antitrust as the central cause of many of our social and economic problems, while I see other public policy failures—including weak voter-protection and anti-corruption laws, inadequate protections for workers, highly unequal access to education and health care, and a tax system that contains many regressive elements—as the central culprits. Indeed, many of the social and economic problems we are facing in the United States today can also be found in countries such as the U.K. and France, where competition policy has by no means been captured by free market ideology.
The Populists also implicate the use of economics in antitrust as counterproductive. Obviously, I strongly disagree with that assessment. Antitrust is about economic concepts, and the problems with antitrust law have come when it has departed from economic learning. Economics is a neutral tool that helps us understand the economic effects of various business practices. Louis Brandeis himself was deeply concerned about real economic effects, not legal formalisms.
What do these differences in diagnosis imply for antitrust policy? There are a number of distinct Populist voices, and the Populist approach to antitrust is still evolving, but some clear themes have emerged. For starters, Modernists and Populists agree on many antitrust policy proposals that would reverse the Chicago School excesses. As one example, they agree that the Biden administration should rescind the Trump administration’s misguided and poorly reasoned approach to standard-essential patents. Both camps want more vigorous antitrust enforcement.
But there are some major differences between the policy proposals of the Populists and the Modernists, which stem from fundamental differences in what they want antitrust to accomplish. The Populists want to use antitrust to deconcentrate private power, while the Modernists want antitrust to protect and promote competition. Populists associate the “Curse of Bigness” with large firms, while Modernists recognize that many “superstar firms” have grown large by being highly efficient.
Here is a good litmus test: What should be done with companies that grow organically and come to have durable monopoly power solely as a result of effectively and efficiently serving the needs of their customers? Populists are quite willing to break up such companies. Modernists are not.
The basic idea of deconcentrating the U.S. economy to disperse private power is not new. In 1969, the Neal Report recommended that Congress pass the Concentrated Industries Act, which would have empowered the Attorney General to break up “oligopoly industries” so that the leading firm’s market share would be no larger than 12.5 percent.
William Kovacic has masterfully explained the recurrent impulse to use antitrust to break up large firms, and why this impulse has repeatedly met with failure. He also astutely predicted, some 30 years ago, that the impulse would emerge again.
Why, then, will a new collection of enforcement officials set off to climb a mountain that routinely has conquered its challengers? The answer may be that the durability of the deconcentration impulse ultimately has little to do with realistic expectations that a broad-based program of Sherman Act divestiture suits will dissolve existing aggregations of market power. Its recurring hold on public policy instead derives from its attractiveness as a symbolic outlet for public antipathy toward large corporate size.
Breaking up successful, efficient, and innovative companies merely because they have grown too large or powerful is antithetical to the competitive process. Economic theory and evidence indicate that a widespread campaign to break up large firms on a “no-fault” basis would slow economic growth by making our economy less competitive and less innovative. So would imposing line of business restrictions that block firms from exploiting economies of scope and thereby injecting competition into adjacent markets. In my opinion, these blunt deconcentration policies would cause the prices of many goods and services to go up, harming many American households. More fundamentally, breaking up monopolies and oligopolies on a “no-fault” basis would be fighting against powerful, underlying economic forces associated with economies of scale and scope that are a pervasive feature of advanced economies around the world.
In any event, I do not believe that the American people would tolerate an economic system under which successful firms that have done nothing wrong are routinely broken up by the government. I shudder to think what Donald J. Trump would have done with that power, and I doubt very much that Congress will want to put such power in the hands of the executive branch. I hope not.
As much as I am concerned about the excessive political power of large corporations in the United States, I do not see widespread deconcentration of the economy as a wise response. The economic costs would be enormous. If there is sufficient political will to reduce the political power of large corporations, there are far better solutions that would not cause such damage to our economy. For example, shareholder votes could be required for any political contributions by public companies, public funding of candidates could be increased, and vastly more transparency into how corporations interact with and lobby the government could be mandated.
Conclusion
Antitrust law urgently needs to free itself of the laissez-faire ideology that the Chicago School has successfully embedded into the case law over the past several decades. This article explains how that can be done by replacing Chicago School doctrine with a constellation of rebuttable presumptions favoring antitrust plaintiffs that are based on economic theory and evidence. I hope that Modernists and Populists will make common cause with this effort.
In the months and years ahead, I expect to see the Biden administration generally pushing the boundaries of antitrust enforcement in a pragmatic way, recognizing that the case law in many respects is favorable to defendants and that losing cases weakens enforcement. I especially expect—and hope—to see challenges in cases where dominant firms are seeking to acquire nascent competitors that pose a real threat to their dominance. Protecting competition requires preserving those threats, especially when they are few in number. Those cases will likely involve both horizontal and vertical issues. How the agencies and the courts deal with the inherent difficulty of predicting the path of innovation and with claimed synergies will be critical.
We also will see a noticeable increase in enforcement activity if Congress substantially increases the budgets of the enforcement agencies. Those extra resources would do a great deal to turbocharge the efforts of the Biden administration to better deter anticompetitive mergers and conduct and to push the boundaries of antitrust law.
Finally, we have the prospect of major, substantive changes to the antitrust statutes to strengthen antitrust enforcement. Others are more qualified than I am to assess the likelihood of Congress passing such legislation, but if it does, we will see a wave of cases testing the boundaries of these new provisions. I would like to think that the courts would then get the message and finally move past the Chicago School biases against antitrust plaintiffs that have seeped into the case law over the years. Only time will tell.